02 May 2013

Notes - Bkgd. Human Will w/ Brothers 17 / Lake and Desert Rim / Summary: Will / Memory


         You woke up in the light but before the sun. Breakfast and the paper are done and you are thinking on a nap. Earlier this morning you remembered what you had forgotten yesterday, the connection built in -- or, how pets sometimes turn out to look like their masters. Unconscious replications almost invisible that allow people to be chameleon-like, to adapt in physical ways, and you wonder of this is true in the realm of heartansoulanmind.

         0844 hours. I have on an old thin-striped short sleeve shirt and I am reminded of the clothing seen on those once incarcerated in Dachau and Auschwitz. This then reflects on the Nuremberg rallies.

** **
The Nuremberg Rally (officially Reichsparteitag, meaning Reich party convention) was the annual rally of the Nazi Party in Germany, held from 1923 to 1938. They were large Nazi propaganda events, especially after Hitler's rise to power in 1933. These events were held at the Nazi party rally grounds in Nuremberg from 1933 to 1938 and are usually referred to in English as the Nuremberg Rallies. Many films were made to commemorate them, the most famous of which is Triumph of the Will.

Edited from Wikipedia
** **
         Will needs to be defined.

** **
Will (philosophy)
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Will, in philosophy, refers to a property of the mind, and an attribute of acts intentionally performed. Actions made according to a person's will are called “willing” or “voluntary” and sometimes pejoratively “willful” or “at will”. In general, "will" does not refer to one particular or most preferred desire but rather to the general capacity to have such desires and act decisively based on them, according to whatever criteria the willing agent applies. The will is in turn important within philosophy because a person's will is one of the most distinct parts of their mind, along with reason and understanding. It is one of the things, which makes a person who they are, and it is especially important in ethics, because it is the part, which determines whether people act, at least when they act deliberately.
One of the repeating questions discussed in the Western philosophical tradition since Christianization is the question of "free will", and the related but more general notion of fate, which asks how will can be truly free if the actions of people have natural or divine causes which determine them, but which are not really under the control of people. The question is directly connected to discussions of what Freedom is, and also the "problem of evil", because it brings into question whether people really cause their own acts.

Classical philosophy

The classical treatment of the ethical importance of will is to be found in the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle, Books III and Book VII. These discussions have been a major influence in the development of ethical and legal thinking in western civilization.
In Book III Aristotle divided actions into three categories instead of two:

•               Voluntary (ekousion) acts.
•                
•               Involuntary or unwilling (akousion) acts, which are in the simplest case where people do not praise or blame. In such cases a person does not choose the wrong thing, for example if the wind carries a person off, or if a person has a wrong understanding of the particular facts of a situation. Note that ignorance of what aims are good and bad, such as people of bad character always have, is not something people typically excuse as ignorance in this sense. "Acting on account of ignorance seems different from acting while being ignorant".
•                
•               "Non-voluntary" or "non willing" actions (ouk ekousion) which are bad actions done by choice, or more generally (as in the case of animals and children when desire or spirit causes an action) whenever "the source of the moving of the parts that are instrumental in such actions is in oneself" and anything "up to oneself either to do or not". However, these actions are not taken because they are preferred in their own right, but rather because all options available are worse.
•                
It is concerning this third class of actions that there is doubt about whether they should be praised or blamed or condoned in different cases.

Virtue and vice according to Aristotle are "up to us". This means that although no one is willingly unhappy, vice by definition always involves actions, which were decided upon willingly. Vice comes from bad habits and aiming at the wrong things, not deliberately aiming to be unhappy. The vices then, are voluntary just as the virtues are. He states that people would have to be unconscious not to realize the importance of allowing themselves, to live badly, and he dismisses any idea that different people have different innate visions of what is good.

In Book VII, Aristotle discusses self-mastery, or the difference between what people decide to do, and what they actually do. For Aristotle, akrasia, "unrestraint", is distinct from animal-like behavior because it is specific to humans and involves conscious rational thinking about what to do, even though the conclusions of this thinking are not put into practice. When someone behaves in a purely animal-like way, then for better or worse they are not acting based upon any conscious choice.

Aristotle also addresses a few questions raised earlier, on the basis of what he has explained:-

•               Not everyone who stands firm on the basis of a rational and even correct decision has self-mastery. Stubborn people are actually more like a person without self-mastery, because they are partly led by the pleasure coming from victory.
•                
•               Not everyone who fails to stand firm on the basis of his best deliberations has a true lack of self mastery. As an example he gives the case of Neoptolemus (in Sophocles' Philoctetes) refusing to lie despite being part of a plan he agreed with.
•                
•               A person with practical wisdom (phronesis) can not have akrasia. Instead it might sometimes seem so, because mere cleverness can sometimes recite words which might make them sound wise, like an actor or a drunk person reciting poetry. A person lacking self-mastery can have knowledge, but not an active knowledge that they are paying attention to. For example when someone is in a state such as being drunk or enraged, people may have knowledge, and even show that they have that knowledge, like an actor, but not be using it.

Medieval European philosophy

Inspired by Islamic philosophers Avicenna and Averroes, Aristotelian philosophy became part of a standard approach to all legal and ethical discussion in Europe by the time of Thomas Aquinas. His philosophy can be seen as a synthesis of Aristotle and early Christian doctrine as formulated by Boethius and Augustine of Hippo, although sources such as Maimonides and Plato and the aforementioned Muslim scholars are also cited.
With the use of Scholasticism, Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologica makes a structured treatment of the concept of will. A very simple representation of this treatment may look like this:
•               Does the will desire nothing? (No.)
•               Does it desire all things of necessity, whatever it desires? (No.)
•               Is it a higher power than the intellect? (No.)
•               Does the will move the intellect? (Yes.)
•               Is the will divided into irascible and concupiscible? (No.)

This is related to the following points on free will:
•               Does man have free-will? (Yes.)
•               What is free-will—a power, an act, or a habit? (A power.)
•               If it is a power, is it appetitive or cognitive? (Appetitive.)
•               If it is appetitive, is it the same power as the will, or distinct? (The same, with contingencies).

Early modern philosophy

The use of English in philosophical publications began in the early modern period, and therefore the English word "will" became a term used in philosophical discussion. During this same period, Scholasticism, which had largely been a Latin language movement, was heavily criticized. Both Francis Bacon and Rene Descartes described the human intellect or understanding as something which needed to be considered limited, and needing the help of a methodical and skeptical approach to learning about nature. Bacon emphasized the importance analyzing experience in an organized way, for example experimentation, while Descartes, seeing the success of Galileo in using mathematics in physics, emphasized the role of methodical reasoning as in mathematics and geometry. Descartes specifically said that error comes about because the will is not limited to judging things which the understanding is limited to, and described the possibility of such judging or choosing things ignorantly, without understanding them, as free will.

Under the influence of Bacon and Descartes, Thomas Hobbes made one of the first attempts to systematically analyze ethical and political matters in a modern way. He defined will in his Leviathan Chapter VI, in words which explicitly criticize the medieval scholastic definitions:

In deliberation, the last appetite, or aversion, immediately adhering to the action, or to the omission thereof, is that we call the will; the act, not the faculty, of willing. And beasts that have deliberation, must necessarily also have will. The definition of the will, given commonly by the Schools, that it is a rational appetite, is not good. For if it were, then could there be no voluntary act against reason. For a voluntary act is that, which proceedeth from the will, and no other. But if instead of a rational appetite, we shall say an appetite resulting from a precedent deliberation, then the definition is the same that I have given here. Will therefore is the last appetite in deliberating. And though we say in common discourse, a man had a will once to do a thing that nevertheless he forbore to do; yet that is properly but an inclination, which makes no action voluntary; because the action depends not of it, but of the last inclination, or appetite. For if the intervenient appetites, make any action voluntary; then by the same reason all intervenient aversions, should make the same action involuntary; and so one and the same action, should be both voluntary and involuntary.

By this it is manifest, that not only actions that have their beginning from covetousness, ambition, lust, or other appetites to the thing propounded; but also those that have their beginning from aversion, or fear of those consequences that follow the omission, are voluntary actions.

Concerning "free will", most early modern philosophers, including Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke and Hume believed that the term was frequently used in a wrong or illogical sense, and that the philosophical problems concerning any difference between "will" and "free will" are due to verbal confusion (because all will is free):

a FREEMAN, is he, that in those things, which by his strength and wit he is able to do, is not hindered to do what he has a will to. But when the words free, and liberty, are applied to any thing but bodies, they are abused; for that which is not subject to motion, is not subject to impediment: and therefore, when it is said, for example, the way is free, no liberty of the way is signified, but of those that walk in it without stop. And when we say a gift is free, there is not meant any liberty of the gift, but of the giver, that was not bound by any law or covenant to give it. So when we speak freely, it is not the liberty of voice, or pronunciation, but of the man, whom no law hath obliged to speak otherwise than he did. Lastly, from the use of the word free-will, no liberty can be inferred of the will, desire, or inclination, but the liberty of the man; which consisteth in this, that he finds no stop, in doing what he has the will, desire, or inclination to do.."

Spinoza argues that seemingly "free" actions aren't actually free, or that the entire concept is a chimera because "internal" beliefs are necessarily caused by earlier external events. The appearance of the internal is a mistake rooted in ignorance of causes, not in an actual volition, and therefore the will is always determined. Spinoza also rejects teleology, and suggests that the causal nature along with an originary orientation of the universe is everything we encounter.

Some generations later, David Hume made a very similar point to Hobbes in other words:
But to proceed in this reconciling project with regard to the question of liberty and necessity; the most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious science; it will not require many words to prove, that all mankind have ever agreed in the doctrine of liberty as well as in that of necessity, and that the whole dispute, in this respect also, has been hitherto merely verbal. For what is meant by liberty, when applied to voluntary actions? We cannot surely mean that actions have so little connexion with motives, inclinations, and circumstances, that one does not follow with a certain degree of uniformity from the other, and that one affords no inference by which we can conclude the existence of the other. For these are plain and acknowledged matters of fact. By liberty, then, we can only mean a power of acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the will; that is, if we choose to remain at rest, we may; if we choose to move, we also may. Now this hypothetical liberty is universally allowed to belong to every one who is not a prisoner and in chains. Here, then, is no subject of dispute.

Rousseau

Jean-Jacques Rousseau added a new type of will to those discussed by philosophers, which he called the "General will" (volonté générale). This concept developed from Rousseau's considerations on the social contract theory of Hobbes, and describes the shared will of a whole citizenry, whose agreement is understood to exist in discussions about the legitimacy of governments and laws.

Kant

Kant's Transcendental Idealism claimed that "all objects are mere appearances [phenomena]." He asserted that "nothing whatsoever can ever be said about the thing in itself that may be the basis of these appearances." Kant's critics responded by saying that Kant had no right, therefore, to assume the existence of a thing in itself.

Schopenhauer

Schopenhauer disagreed with Kant's critics and stated that it is absurd to assume that phenomena have no basis. Schopenhauer proposed that we cannot know the thing in itself as though it is a cause of phenomena. Instead, he said that we can know it by knowing our own body, which is the only thing that we can know at the same time as both a phenomenon and a thing in itself.

When we become conscious of ourself, we realize that our essential qualities are endless urging, craving, striving, wanting, and desiring. These are characteristics of that which we call our will. Schopenhauer affirmed that we can legitimately think that all other phenomena are also essentially and basically will. According to him, will "is the innermost essence, the kernel, of every particular thing and also of the whole. It appears in every blindly acting force of nature, and also in the deliberate conduct of man…." Schopenhauer said that his predecessors mistakenly thought that the will depends on knowledge. According to him, though, the will is primary and uses knowledge in order to find an object that will satisfy its craving. That which, in us, we call will is Kant's "thing in itself", according to Schopenhauer.

Arthur Schopenhauer put the puzzle of free will and moral responsibility in these terms:
Everyone believes himself a priori to be perfectly free, even in his individual actions, and thinks that at every moment he can commence another manner of life. ... But a posteriori, through experience, he finds to his astonishment that he is not free, but subjected to necessity, that in spite of all his resolutions and reflections he does not change his conduct, and that from the beginning of his life to the end of it, he must carry out the very character which he himself condemns...

In his On the Freedom of the Will, Schopenhauer stated, "You can do what you will, but in any given moment of your life you can will only one definite thing and absolutely nothing other than that one thing."

Nietzsche

Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzche was influenced by Schopenhauer when younger, but later felt him to be wrong. However, he maintained a modified focus upon will, making the term "will to power" famous as an explanation of human aims and actions.

Idealism: Will as all

In idealistic models of reality, the material world is either non-existent or is a secondary artifact of the "true" world of ideas. In such worlds, it can be said that everything is an act of will. Even if you are arrested by the police, this is actually an act of your will, too; if you didn't want it to happen, you could have decided otherwise. This line of thought is seen among proponents of a spiritual or mystical universe such as Carlos Castaneda, the New Thought writers Frank Channing Haddock (The Power of Will) and William Walker Atkinson (Personal Power Volume V: Will Power).

The concept of Will is especially important to certain Hermetic and esoteric traditions, particularly in and those mystical practices associated with European ideology. Perhaps most notably, the concept takes on an essential role as the philosophical-spiritual basis of Thelema (and its various delineations), an occultic system of thought developed by the writer-mystic Aleister Crowley: Crowley argued that Will provides for a certain ground of being, as well as the possibility that rituals such as ceremonial magic, yoga, and meditation allow for conscious beings to have direct influence over reality and both the spiritual and metaphysical world. Important to Thelema (the term itself meaning "will") is the notion of a difference between mundane "will" and True Will, the latter of which is the purposed fulfillment of human beings through a process of [largely esoteric] methods employed to achieve self-realization.

Edited from Wikipedia - Will (Philosophy)
** **

         What an excellent summary this Wikipedia provides.

         Most of this is re-enforcer to what you have already read at one time or another. Your editing for these notes will retag unconsciously concealed reminders of what needs to be expressed in Brothers 17. Study the above closely. - Amorella

         0937 hours. This will take more study. I will put this on a separate document and divide the content into a flow my mind can more easily render.

         Later, orndorff. Post. - Amorella


         1130 hours. The sun is coming out, did some yard chores and we are readying to go to Pine Hill Lakes Park for a walk, a short walk for me. I did too much work yesterday, no exercises today. Carol is talking to Wandy F., at the third house to our north and east. Dennis F. is her husband and he took over as head of the volunteer Lakeside community government on which Carol served for several years. Mr. Bob Austermann, our neighbor, next to the King's next door to the south was head of Lakeside for its first nineteen years; he is now in his mid-eighties.

         You walked a bit, over along the big lake and you took a couple of photos on your iPhone. Drop these in later and Robert and Richard can be sitting on a bench in Riverton Lakes Park talking. - Amorella

         I would like that, I would like to be talking to Bob once again even in memory and invention.

         Good. From a Bible in Brothers 16 to philosophy in Brothers 17, pretty standard fare. - Amorella

         Yes, it was. (1224) I'm waiting on Carol to complete her walk. Earlier I was sitting on a bench talking to one of Tim King's students -- they are fly fishing in his Words in the Wild (nature/environment writing class). The fellow is a junior. I told him I used to teach at Mason and Indian Hill and to say 'hi' to Tim and to Gary (Mr. Popplewell) who is my closest long time friend in my Mason teaching days (1984 - 2003). Indian Hill was during the 1972 - 1984 school years. Escola Graduada de Sao Paulo took place in 1970 - 1972. Whitehall-Yearling took place in 1967 - 1969, and Magnetic Springs Junior High was 1966 - 1967. In the Spring of 1966 I did my student teaching an Olentangy High School.

         You split a full course turkey breast and black forest ham, nine-grain honey oat foot long Subway sub, a pack of chips and two cookies. Carol brought her own ice tea and you picked up a large Coke Zero at the store. You are down at the park along the Little Miami amongst the leafing trees and green grass.



Looking south from east side Pine Hill Lake
(Mason fly fisherman climbing the bank from Mr. King's Class)



Looking north from east side Pine Hill Lake

         We will encompass these photos in Brothers 17. While you were downloading photos you had some from the Grand Canyon Desert Rim. There are three in particular that I like. Drop them here. - Amorella

** **


Looking North - Colorado River below
with East Desert Rim midway on the upper right



Looking northeast at the East Desert Rim



Looking east at the East Desert Rim

** **

          1440 hours. I am surprised. You usually don't have much to say about such photos other than: "This is not a travel log."

         In here, these three photos represent the land (if you will) between the Living and the Dead or as they used to say, between the Quick and the Dead. The "heart of darkness" (no offense to Joseph Conrad) is an illusion. This is Merlyn's upcoming point in Brothers 17. Post. - Amorella 


         1739 hours. I have summarized what may be needed on "Human Will" for Brothers 17 as well as perhaps later in the GMG series.

         Add here and post. - Amorella

***
HUMAN WILL (PHILOSOPHY) refers to a property of the mind, and an attribute of acts intentionally performed.   [Wikipedia summarized by rho]

Actions made according to a person's will are called “willing” or “voluntary” and sometimes pejoratively “willful” or “at will”.

The will is in turn important within philosophy because a person's will is one of the most distinct parts of their mind, along with reason and understanding.

It is especially important in ethics, because it is the part, which determines whether people act, at least when they act deliberately.

How can will be truly free if the actions of people have natural or divine causes which determine them, but which are not really under the control of people?

It brings into question whether people really cause their own acts.

Classical philosophy

Aristotle divided actions into three categories instead of two:

•               Voluntary (ekousion) acts.
                
•               Involuntary or unwilling (akousion) acts, which are in the simplest case where people do not praise or blame.
                
•               "Non-voluntary" or "non willing" actions (ouk ekousion) which are bad actions done by choice.

Virtue and vice according to Aristotle are "up to us". This means that although no one is willingly unhappy, vice by definition always involves actions, which were decided upon willingly.

Vice comes from bad habits and aiming at the wrong things, not deliberately aiming to be unhappy. The vices then, are voluntary just as the virtues are.

Aristotle discusses self-mastery, or the difference between what people decide to do, and what they actually do.

A person lacking self-mastery can have knowledge, but not an active knowledge that they are paying attention to.
People may have knowledge, and even show that they have that knowledge, like an actor, but not be using it.

Medieval European philosophy

With the use of Scholasticism, Thomas Aquinas's Summa Theologica makes a structured treatment of the concept of will. A very simple representation of this treatment may look like this:

•               Does the will desire nothing? (No.)

•               Does it desire all things of necessity, whatever it desires? (No.)

•               Is it a higher power than the intellect? (No.)

•               Does the will move the intellect? (Yes.)

•               Is the will divided into irascible and concupiscible? (No.)

This is related to the following points on free will:

•               Does man have free-will? (Yes.)

•               What is free-will—a power, an act, or a habit? (A power.)

•               If it is a power, is it appetitive or cognitive? (Appetitive.)

•               If it is appetitive, is it the same power as the will, or distinct? (The same, with                  contingencies).

Early modern philosophy

The use of English in philosophical publications began in the early modern period, and therefore the English word "will" became a term used in philosophical discussion. During this same period, Scholasticism, which had largely been a Latin language movement, was heavily criticized.

In deliberation, the last appetite, or aversion, immediately adhering to the action, or to the omission thereof, is that we call the will; the act, not the faculty, of willing.

Will therefore is the last appetite in deliberating. And though we say in common discourse, a man had a will once to do a thing that nevertheless he forbore to do; yet that is properly but an inclination, which makes no action voluntary; because the action depends not of it, but of the last inclination, or appetite.

Concerning "free will", most early modern philosophers, including Hobbes, Spinoza, Locke and Hume believed that the term was frequently used in a wrong or illogical sense, and that the philosophical problems concerning any difference between "will" and "free will" are due to verbal confusion (because all will is free).

Some generations later, David Hume made a very similar point to Hobbes in other words:

But to proceed in this reconciling project with regard to the question of liberty and necessity; the most contentious question of metaphysics, the most contentious science; it will not require many words to prove, that all mankind have ever agreed in the doctrine of liberty as well as in that of necessity, and that the whole dispute, in this respect also, has been hitherto merely verbal. For what is meant by liberty, when applied to voluntary actions?
By liberty, then, we can only mean a power of acting or not acting, according to the determinations of the will; that is, if we choose to remain at rest, we may; if we choose to move, we also may. Now this hypothetical liberty is universally allowed to belong to every one who is not a prisoner and in chains. Here, then, is no subject of dispute.
Rousseau

Jean-Jacques Rousseau added a new type of will to those discussed by philosophers, which he called the "General will". This concept developed from Rousseau's considerations on the social contract theory of Hobbes, and describes the shared will of a whole citizenry, whose agreement is understood to exist in discussions about the legitimacy of governments and laws.

Kant

Kant's Transcendental Idealism claimed, "all objects are mere appearances [phenomena]." He asserted, "nothing whatsoever can ever be said about the thing in itself that may be the basis of these appearances." Kant's critics responded by saying that Kant had no right, therefore, to assume the existence of a thing in itself.

Schopenhauer

Schopenhauer proposed that we cannot know the thing in itself as though it is a cause of phenomena. Instead, he said that we can know it by knowing our own body, which is the only thing that we can know at the same time as both a phenomenon and a thing in itself.

When we become conscious of ourselves, we realize that our essential qualities are endless urging, craving, striving, wanting, and desiring. These are characteristics of that which we call our will.

According to him, though, the will is primary and uses knowledge in order to find an object that will satisfy its craving. That which, in us, we call will is Kant's "thing in itself", according to Schopenhauer.

Everyone believes himself a priori to be perfectly free, even in his individual actions, and thinks that at every moment he can commence another manner of life. ... But a posteriori, through experience, he finds to his astonishment that he is not free, but subjected to necessity, that in spite of all his resolutions and reflections he does not change his conduct, and that from the beginning of his life to the end of it, he must carry out the very character which he himself condemns...

In his On the Freedom of the Will, Schopenhauer stated, "You can do what you will, but in any given moment of your life you can will only one definite thing and absolutely nothing other than that one thing."

Nietzsche

Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche maintained a modified focus upon will, making the term "will to power" famous as an explanation of human aims and actions.

Idealism: Will as all

In idealistic models of reality, the material world is either non-existent or is a secondary artifact of the "true" world of ideas. In such worlds, it can be said that everything is an act of will.

This line of thought is seen among proponents of a spiritual or mystical universe such as Carlos Castaneda. [A Separate Reality]

The concept of Will is especially important to certain Hermetic and esoteric traditions, particularly in and those mystical practices associated with European ideology.

Aleister Crowley (writer-mystic) argued that Will provides for a certain ground of being, as well as the possibility that rituals such as ceremonial magic, yoga, and meditation allow for conscious beings to have direct influence over reality and both the spiritual and metaphysical world.

The notion of a difference between mundane "will" and True Will, the latter of which is the purposed fulfillment of human beings through a process of [largely esoteric] methods employed to achieve self-realization.

Edited & Compressed from Wikipedia - Will (Philosophy)
***


         The last of Alta's Arizona turkey soup for supper and you watched two "NCIS" shows and one "Castle" from your vacation DVRing. The windows are open upstairs and you both are ready for another good night's sleep in comfortable early morning outside temperatures.

         2151 hours. I feel ready to begin and perhaps to conclude Brothers 17 tomorrow. What sparks the discussion?

         Why the two took the separate tracks they took professionally, heart surgeon and college professor. Originally both had planned to make the USAF their careers. The girls were going to join the Peace Corps. The Cuban Missile Crisis and the assassination of JFK changed their lives. The theme is "how things come about". - Amorella

         Why all the background?

         Because both loved philosophy in those days -- avid readers. Both sets of parents pressed them to develop independently so they might grow to be free financially. You will have to go back to their sophomore years in college. Freshman year 1960-1961; Sophomore: 1961-1962; Junior: 1962-1963; Senior: 1963-1964. Those will be the years of focus. Tomorrow, dude. Post. - Amorella

         2212 hours. This seems like far too much to put in 750 words.

         Put your memory into it, you'll see how easy this will be. - Amorella



No comments:

Post a Comment