Morning. Jill arrived to clean a day early. Fortunately all is well. It
is a beautiful day. (Note. You forgot how to spell beautiful.) - Amorella
1034 hours. It is amazing that I can see a word I have known how to
spell since forever and nothing registers spelling wise, that is between the
'be' and 'tiful'.
This doesn't happen often, but it happens. I've
written about this spelling problem before but as I get older, it may become more
of a concern.
More later, dude. - Amorella
1043
hours. I need to define 'spiritual'.
** **
Spiritual - adjective 1. relating to or affecting the human spirit or soul as opposed to material or physical things: I'm
responsible for his spiritual welfare | the
spiritual values of life.
Spirit - noun1 the nonphysical part of a person which
is the seat of emotions and character; the soul: we
seek a harmony between body and spirit. • the nonphysical part of a person regarded as
a person's true self and as capable of surviving physical death or separation: a
year after he left, his spirit is still present. • the nonphysical part of a person manifested as an
apparition after their death; a ghost. • a supernatural being: shrines
to nature spirits. • (the Spirit) short
for Holy Spirit.
Holy Spirit - noun (in Christianity) the
third person of the Trinity; God as spiritually active in the world.
Selected
and edited from the Oxford/American software.
** **
1051
hours. I am surprised by these definitions for example: "affecting the
human spirit or soul". I do not see the spirit and the soul as the same
thing.
** **
soul - noun 1. the spiritual or
immaterial part of a human being or animal, regarded as immortal. • a person's moral or
emotional nature or sense of identity: in
the depths of her soul, she knew he would betray her.
Selected
and edited from the Oxford/American software
** **
1057
hours. Even the Oxford/American shows the difference in that both spiritual and
soul are considered immortal. I agree but the soul is not the spirit.
You are arrogant. How do you explain the
difference, boy? - Amorella
1100 hours. The soul is a part of the human spirit, that's our
definition.
It is; but this blog is partially a hypothesis,
a proposed explanation is it not? - Amorella
1105 hours. It is. Okay, but why the 'person' in the Holy Spirit? Surely
the Holy Spirit is not three people. I don't get how one can read this and not
see something is not correct in this definition; in a dictionary no less.
Look at the errors in your blog, boy. Who is
calling the kettle black? Post. - Amorella
Quantum
superposition
Physical interpretation
Consciousness
1.
History of the issue
2.
Concepts of Consciousness
2.1
Creature Consciousness
2.2
State consciousness
2.3 Consciousness
as an entity
3.
Problems of Consciousness
4.
The descriptive question: What are the features of consciousness?
4.1
First-person and third-person data
4.2
Qualitative character
4.3
Phenomenal structure
4.4
Subjectivity ***
4.5
Self-perspectival organization
4.6
Unity
4.7
Intentionality and transparency
4.8
Dynamic flow
5.
The explanatory question: How can consciousness exist?
5.1
Diversity of explanatory projects
5.2
The explanatory gap
5.3
Reductive and non-reductive explanation
5.4 Prospects
of explanatory success
6.
The functional question: Why does consciousness exist?
6.1
Causal status of consciousness
6.2
Flexible control
6.3
Social coordination
6.4
Integrated representation
6.5
Informational access
6.6
Freedom of will
6.7
Intrinsic motivation
6.8
Constitutive and contingent roles
7.
Theories of consciousness
8.
Metaphysical theories of consciousness
8.1
Dualist theories
8.2
Physicalist theories
9.
Specific Theories of Consciousness
9.1
Higher-order theories
9.2
Reflexive theories
9.3
Representationalist theories
9.4
Narrative Interpretative Theories
9.5
Cognitive Theories
9.6
Information Integration Theory
9.7
Neural Theories
9.8
Quantum theories
9.9
Non-physical theories
10.
Conclusion
We
can do this. Make a copy on a separate document and we'll tear it down to what
is appropriate for consciousness and mind as in heartansoulanmind. For now,
take a break and post. - Amorella
You are at Rose Hill Cemetery on the far
west road facing north to be in the shade. You found the article below this
morning and think it may show something about reality that can relate to
consciousness. You have underlined what may be useful to your thinking. -
Amorella
** **
From Your
Quora Digest
Quantum mechanics states that you
cannot precisely measure both position and momentum. Just because you can't
measure it, doesn't mean it doesn't have position and momentum at the same
time. The theory seems based on this principle, but why?
Viktor T. Toth, IT pro,
part-time physicist
Answered Oct 31 ·
Upvoted by Frederic Rachford,
PhD Physics, Case Western Reserve University (1975) and Jesse Raffield, Master's degree in physics
|
No, quantum mechanics does not state that you cannot
simultaneously measure both position and momentum precisely. It is a
consequence of the theory, but it is not what the theory is based on.
Quantum mechanics states that a classical position, classical
momentum, or other classical observables do not exist except in the rare cases
when the quantum object interacts with something classical (such as an
instrument.)
When you look at the mathematics (and you have to look at the
mathematics; quantum mechanics cannot be intuited) something amazing emerges. The
formal equations of quantum mechanics, such as the Schrödinger equation, can be
“derived” easily from classical physics. However, this equation offers many
more solutions than its classical counterpart. Quantum mechanics begins when we
look at these solutions and accept them as valid descriptions of reality,
despite the fact that they seemingly make no intuitive sense, certainly not in
the context of classical physics.
Now you
may wonder, what on Earth possesses us to go down this rabbit hole? Very
simple: physics is based on experiment and observation. And we found that this
is how the physical world works.
When we
look at this much richer world of quantum solutions, we find that indeed, most
of the time that particle does not have a classical position or a classical
momentum. Moreover, the math tells us, when it is confined to a classical
position by a measurement, its classical momentum does not exist; it remains in
a superposition of states.
So when you think of an electron inside a cathode ray tube,
going from the cathode to the screen while mysteriously going through two holes
at the same time, and ask yourself, “What was the electron’s path?”,
unfortunately the only legitimate answer sounds just as mysterious as the
little boy telling Neo in the film The Matrix that there is no spoon:
There is no (classical) path. It’s not that we cannot measure it. It truly
does not exist. And whether we like it or not, that’s the way Nature works. But
there is one advantage that we have over a piece of fiction like The Matrix:
our outlandish statement is grounded in firm mathematics that leads to testable
predictions, through which our outlandish claims can be (and have been,
countless times) verified and validated
Selected
and edited from QuoraDOTcom, 14
November 17
** **
1220
hours. Now that I read over it again I don't see a connection to consciousness or
to the heartansoulanmind.
When reading the selection I just bolded you
will see a connection can be made.
** **
When we
look at this much richer world of quantum solutions, we find that indeed, most
of the time that particle does not have a classical position or a classical
momentum. Moreover, the math tells us, when it is confined to a classical
position by a measurement, its classical momentum does not exist; it remains in
a superposition of states.
** **
It may be possible that 'heartansoulanmind'
or 'the human spirit' is not measurable because it is in a superposition of
states. - Amorella
You had a refreshing experience eating at
the new Panera near Kroger's and I-71. Now you are sitting at the far north lot
at Pine Hill Lakes. - Amorella
1352 hours. I am including two definitions (both partial as I dropped
the math equations). The first is from WhatIs, the second from Wikipedia.
** **
Definition selected and
edited from - WhatIs DOT com
Posted by: Margaret Rouse; Contributor(s): Jon Kim
superposition
Superposition is the ability of a
quantum system to be in multiple states at the same time until it is
measured.
Because
the concept is difficult to understand, this essential principle of quantum
mechanics is often illustrated by an experiment carried out in 1801 by
the English physicist, Thomas Young. Young's double-slit experiment was
intended to prove that light consists of waves. Today, the experiment is used
to help people understand the way that electrons can act like waves and create
interference patterns.
For
this experiment, a beam of light is aimed at a barrier with two vertical slits.
The light passes through the slits and the resulting pattern is recorded on a
photographic plate. When one slit is covered, the pattern is what would be
expected: a single line of light, aligned with whichever slit is open.
Intuitively,
one would expect that if both slits are open, the pattern of light will reflect
two lines of light aligned with the slits. In fact, what happens is that the
photographic plate separates into multiple lines of lightness and darkness in
varying degrees.
What
is being illustrated by this result is that interference is taking place
between the waves going through the slits, in what, seemingly, should be two
non-crossing trajectories. Each photon not only goes through both slits;
it simultaneously takes every possible trajectory en route to the photographic
plate.
In
order to see how this might possibly occur, other experiments have focused on
tracking the paths of individual photons. Surprisingly, the measurement in some
way disrupts the photons' trajectories and somehow, the results of the
experiment become what would be predicted by classical physics: two bright
lines on the photographic plate, each aligned with the slits in the barrier.
This has led scientists to conclude that superposition cannot be directly
observed; one can only observe the resulting consequence, interference.
In
computing, the concept of superposition has important implications for the way
information will be processed and stored in the future. For example, today's
classical computers process information in bits of one or zero, similar to a
light switch being turned on or off. The quantum supercomputers of
tomorrow, however, will process information as qubits -- one, zero or a
superposition of the two states.
This was last updated in
August 2017
** **
** **
Quantum
superposition
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Quantum superposition is a fundamental principle of
quantum mechanics. It states that, much like waves in classical physics, any
two (or more) quantum states can be added together ("superposed") and
the result will be another valid quantum state; and conversely, that every
quantum state can be represented as a sum of two or more other distinct states.
Mathematically, it refers to a property of solutions to the Schrodinger
equation; since the Schrödinger equation is linear, any linear combination of
solutions will also be a solution.
An example of a physically observable manifestation of
superposition is interference peaks from an electron wave in a double-slit
experiment. . . . (drop to the conclusion)
Physical interpretation
It
is natural to ask why ordinary everyday objects and events do not seem to
display quantum mechanical features such as superposition. Indeed, this is
sometimes regarded as "mysterious", for instance by Richard Feynman. In 1935, Erwin Schrodinger devised a well-known thought
experiment, now known as Schrodinger's cat, which highlighted this dissonance
between quantum mechanics and classical physics. The modern view is that this
mystery is explained by quantum decoherence. A macroscopic system (such as a
cat) may evolve over time into a superposition of classically distinct quantum
states (such as "alive" and "dead"). However, the state of
the cat is entangled with the state of its environment (for instance, the
molecules in the atmosphere surrounding it). If one averages over the quantum
states of the environment—a physically reasonable procedure unless the quantum
state of all the particles making up the environment can be controlled or
measured precisely—the resulting mixed quantum state for the cat is very close
to a classical probabilistic state where the cat has some definite probability
to be dead or alive, just as a classical observer would expect in this
situation.
Quantum
superposition is exhibited in fact in many directly observable phenomena, such
as inference peaks from an
electronic wave in a double-slit
experiment. Superposition persists at all scales, provided that coherence is
shielded from disruption by intermittent external factors.
The
Heisenberg uncertainty principle declares
that for any given instant of time, the position and velocity of an electron or
other subatomic particle cannot both be exactly determined, and that a state
where one of them has a definite value corresponds to a superposition of many
states for the other.
Selected
and edited from Wikipedia -
** **
1404
hours. What I wonder is: can superposition be a property of consciousness? Or,
for that matter (pun intended) can superposition be a property of
heartansoulanmind?
Carol is ready to go. She is on page 100/101
of Night School. - Amorella
A stop at Graeters and
Kroger's on Tylersville before heading home. - Amorella
1507 hours. Below are properties/characteristics of consciousness
according to Stanford University online.
** **
Consciousness
First published Fri
Jun 18, 2004; substantive revision Tue Jan 14, 2014
Perhaps
no aspect of mind is more familiar or more puzzling than consciousness and our
conscious experience of self and world. The problem of consciousness is
arguably the central issue in current theorizing about the mind. Despite the
lack of any agreed upon theory of consciousness, there is a widespread, if less
than universal, consensus that an adequate account of mind requires a clear
understanding of it and its place in nature. We need to understand both what
consciousness is and how it relates to other, nonconscious, aspects of reality
1.
History of the issue
Questions
about the nature of conscious awareness have likely been asked for as long as
there have been humans. Neolithic burial practices appear to express spiritual
beliefs and provide early evidence for at least minimally reflective thought
about the nature of human consciousness (Pearson 1999, Clark and Riel-Salvatore
2001). Preliterate cultures have similarly been found invariably to embrace
some form of spiritual or at least animist view that indicates a degree of
reflection about the nature of conscious awareness.
Nonetheless,
some have argued that consciousness as we know it today is a relatively recent
historical development that arose sometime after the Homeric era (Jaynes 1974).
According to this view, earlier humans including those who fought the Trojan
War did not experience themselves as unified internal subjects of their
thoughts and actions, at least not in the ways we do today. Others have claimed
that even during the classical period, there was no word of ancient Greek that
corresponds to “consciousness” (Wilkes 1984, 1988, 1995). Though the ancients
had much to say about mental matters, it is less clear whether they had any
specific concepts or concerns for what we now think of as consciousness.
Although
the words “conscious” and “conscience” are used quite differently today, it is
likely that the Reformation emphasis on the latter as an inner source of truth
played some role in the inward turn so characteristic of the modern reflective
view of self. The Hamlet who walked the stage in 1600 already saw his world and
self with profoundly modern eyes.
By the
beginning of the early modern era in the seventeenth century, consciousness had
come full center in thinking about the mind. Indeed from the mid-17th through
the late 19th century, consciousness was widely regarded as essential or
definitive of the mental. René Descartes defined the very notion of thought (pensée) in terms of
reflexive consciousness or self-awareness. In the Principles
of Philosophy (1640)
he wrote,
By the word ‘thought’
(‘pensée’) I
understand all that of which we are conscious as operating in us.
Later,
toward the end of the 17th century, John Locke offered a similar if slightly
more qualified claim in An Essay on Human Understanding (1688),
I do not say there is
no soul in man because he is not sensible of it in his sleep. But I do say he
cannot think at any time, waking or sleeping, without being sensible of it. Our
being sensible of it is not necessary to anything but our thoughts, and to them
it is and to them it always will be necessary.
Locke explicitly
forswore making any hypothesis about the substantial basis of consciousness and
its relation to matter, but he clearly regarded it as essential to thought as
well as to personal identity.
Locke's
contemporary G.W. Leibniz, drawing possible inspiration from his mathematical
work on differentiation and integration, offered a theory of mind in the Discourse
on Metaphysics (1686)
that allowed for infinitely many degrees of consciousness and perhaps even for
some thoughts that were unconscious, the so called “petites perceptions”.
Leibniz was the first to distinguish explicitly between perception and
apperception, i.e., roughly between awareness and self-awareness. In the Monadology (1720) he also offered his famous
analogy of the mill to express his belief that consciousness could not arise
from mere matter. He asked his reader to imagine someone walking through an
expanded brain as one would walk through a mill and observing all its
mechanical operations, which for Leibniz exhausted its physical nature. Nowhere,
he asserts, would such an observer see any conscious thoughts.
Despite
Leibniz's recognition of the possibility of unconscious thought, for most of
the next two centuries the domains of thought and consciousness were regarded
as more or less the same. Associationist psychology, whether pursued by Locke
or later in the eighteenth century by David Hume (1739) or in the nineteenth by
James Mill (1829), aimed to discover the principles by which conscious thoughts
or ideas interacted or affected each other. James Mill's son, John Stuart Mill
continued his father's work on associationist psychology, but he allowed that
combinations of ideas might produce resultants that went beyond their
constituent mental parts, thus providing an early model of mental emergence
(1865).
The
purely associationist approach was critiqued in the late eighteenth century by
Immanuel Kant (1787), who argued that an adequate account of experience and
phenomenal consciousness required a far richer structure of mental and
intentional organization. Phenomenal consciousness according to Kant could not
be a mere succession of associated ideas, but at a minimum had to be the
experience of a conscious self-situated in an objective world structured with
respect to space, time and causality.
Within
the Anglo-American world, associationist approaches continued to be influential
in both philosophy and psychology well into the twentieth century, while in the
German and European sphere there was a greater interest in the larger structure
of experience that lead in part to the study of phenomenology through the work
of Edmund Husserl (1913, 1929), Martin Heidegger (1927), Maurice Merleau-Ponty
(1945) and others who expanded the study of consciousness into the realm of the
social, the bodily and the interpersonal.
At the
outset of modern scientific psychology in the mid-nineteenth century, the mind
was still largely equated with consciousness, and introspective methods
dominated the field as in the work of Wilhelm Wundt (1897), Hermann von
Helmholtz (1897), William James (1890) and Alfred Titchener (1901). However,
the relation of consciousness to brain remained very much a mystery as
expressed in T. H. Huxley's famous remark,
How it is that
anything so remarkable as a state of consciousness comes about as a result of
irritating nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the appearance of the
Djin, when Aladdin rubbed his lamp (1866).
The early
twentieth century saw the eclipse of consciousness from scientific psychology,
especially in the United States with the rise of behaviorism (Watson 1924,
Skinner 1953) though movements such as Gestalt psychology kept it a matter of
ongoing scientific concern in Europe (Köhler 1929, Köffka 1935). In the 1960s,
the grip of behaviorism weakened with the rise of cognitive psychology and its
emphasis on information processing and the modeling of internal mental
processes (Neisser 1965, Gardiner 1985). However, despite the renewed emphasis
on explaining cognitive capacities such as memory, perception and language comprehension,
consciousness remained a largely neglected topic for several further decades.
In the
1980s and 90s there was a major resurgence of scientific and philosophical
research into the nature and basis of consciousness (Baars 1988, Dennett 1991,
Penrose 1989, 1994, Crick 1994, Lycan 1987, 1996, Chalmers 1996). Once
consciousness was back under discussion, there was a rapid proliferation of
research with a flood of books and articles, as well as the introduction of
specialty journals (The
Journal of Consciousness Studies, Consciousness and Cognition, Psyche), professional societies (Association
for the Scientific Study of Consciousness—ASSC) and annual conferences devoted
exclusively to its investigation (Toward a Science of Consciousness, ASSC).
2.
Concepts of Consciousness
The words
“conscious” and “consciousness” are umbrella terms that cover a wide variety of
mental phenomena. Both are used with a diversity of meanings, and the adjective
“conscious” is heterogeneous in its range, being applied both to whole
organisms—creature consciousness—and to particular mental states and
processes—state consciousness (Rosenthal 1986, Gennaro 1995, Carruthers 2000).
2.1
Creature Consciousness
An
animal, person or other cognitive system may be regarded as conscious in a
number of different senses.
Sentience. It may be conscious in the generic sense of
simply being a sentient creature, one capable of sensing and
responding to its world (Armstrong 1981). Being conscious in this sense may
admit of degrees, and just what sort of sensory capacities are sufficient may
not be sharply defined. Are fish conscious in the relevant respect? And what of
shrimp or bees?
Wakefulness. One might further require that the organism
actually be exercising such a capacity rather than merely having the ability or
disposition to do so. Thus one might count it as conscious only if it were awake
and normally alert. In
that sense organisms would not count as conscious when asleep or in any of the
deeper levels of coma. Again boundaries may be blurry, and intermediate cases
may be involved. For example, is one conscious in the relevant sense when
dreaming, hypnotized or in a fugue state?
Self-consciousness. A third and yet more demanding sense might
define conscious creatures as those that are not only aware but also aware that
they are aware, thus treating creature consciousness as a form of self-consciousness (Carruthers 2000). The self-awareness
requirement might get interpreted in a variety of ways, and which creatures
would qualify as conscious in the relevant sense will vary accordingly. If it
is taken to involve explicit conceptual self-awareness, many non-human animals
and even young children might fail to qualify, but if only more rudimentary
implicit forms of self-awareness are required then a wide range of
nonlinguistic creatures might count as self-conscious.
What it
is like. Thomas
Nagel's (1974) famous “what it
is like” criterion
aims to capture another and perhaps more subjective notion of being a conscious
organism. According to Nagel, a being is conscious just if there is “something
that it is like” to be that creature, i.e., some subjective way the world seems
or appears from the creature's mental or experiential point of view. In Nagel's
example, bats are conscious because there is something that it is like for a
bat to experience its world through its echo-locatory senses, even though we
humans from our human point of view cannot emphatically understand what such a
mode of consciousness is like from the bat's own point of view.
Subject
of conscious states. A fifth
alternative would be to define the notion of a conscious organism in terms of
conscious states. That is, one might first define what makes a mental state a
conscious mental state, and then define being a conscious creature in terms of
having such states. One's concept of a conscious organism would then depend
upon the particular account one gives of conscious states (section 2.2).
Transitive
Consciousness. In
addition to describing creatures as conscious in these various senses, there
are also related senses in which creatures are described as being conscious
of various things. The distinction is sometimes marked as that
between transitive and intransitive notions of consciousness, with the
former involving some object at which consciousness is directed (Rosenthal
1986).
2.2
State consciousness
The
notion of a conscious mental state also has a variety of distinct though
perhaps interrelated meanings. There are at least six major options.
States
one is aware of. On one
common reading, a conscious mental state is simply a mental state one is aware
of being in (Rosenthal 1986, 1996). Conscious states in this sense involve a
form of meta-mentality or meta-intentionality in so far as they require mental
states that are themselves about mental states. To have a conscious desire for
a cup of coffee is to have such a desire and also to be simultaneously and
directly aware that one has such a desire. Unconscious thoughts and desires in
this sense are simply those we have without being aware of having them, whether
our lack of self-knowledge results from simple inattention or more deeply
psychoanalytic causes.
Qualitative
states. States
might also be regarded as conscious in a seemingly quite different and more qualitative sense. That is, one might count a
state as conscious just if it has or involves qualitative or experiential
properties of the sort often referred to as “qualia” or “raw sensory feels”.
(See the entry on qualia.) One's
perception of the Merlot one is drinking or of the fabric one is examining
counts as a conscious mental state in this sense because it involves various
sensory qualia, e.g., taste qualia in the wine case and color qualia in one's
visual experience of the cloth. There is considerable disagreement about the
nature of such qualia (Churchland 1985, Shoemaker 1990, Clark 1993, Chalmers
1996) and even about their existence. Traditionally qualia have been regarded
as intrinsic, private, ineffable monadic features of experience, but current
theories of qualia often reject at least some of those commitments (Dennett
1990).
Phenomenal
states. Such
qualia are sometimes referred to as phenomenal properties and the associated
sort of consciousness as phenomenal consciousness, but the latter term is
perhaps more properly applied to the overall structure of experience and
involves far more than sensory qualia. The phenomenal structure of
consciousness also encompasses much of the spatial, temporal and conceptual
organization of our experience of the world and of ourselves as agents in it.
(See section 4.3) It is
therefore probably best, at least initially, to distinguish the concept of
phenomenal consciousness from that of qualitative consciousness, though they no
doubt overlap.
What-it-is-like
states. Consciousness
in both those senses links up as well with Thomas Nagel's (1974) notion of a
conscious creature, insofar as one might count a mental state as conscious in
the “what it is like” sense just if there is
something that it is like to be in that state. Nagel's criterion might be
understood as aiming to provide a first-person or internal conception of what
makes a state a phenomenal or qualitative state.
Access
consciousness. States
might be conscious in a seemingly quite different access sense, which has more
to do with intra-mental relations. In this respect, a state's being conscious
is a matter of its availability to interact with other states and of the access
that one has to its content. In this more functional sense, which corresponds
to what Ned Block (1995) calls access consciousness, a visual state's being conscious is
not so much a matter of whether or not it has a qualitative “what it's
likeness”, but of whether or not it and the visual information that it carries
is generally available for use and guidance by the organism. In so far as the
information in that state is richly and flexibly available to its containing
organism, then it counts as a conscious state in the relevant respect, whether
or not it has any qualitative or phenomenal feel in the Nagel sense.
Narrative
consciousness. States
might also be regarded as conscious in a narrative sense that appeals to the notion of
the “stream of consciousness”, regarded as an ongoing more or less serial
narrative of episodes from the perspective of an actual or merely virtual self.
The idea would be to equate the person's conscious mental states with those
that appear in the stream (Dennett 1991, 1992).
Although
these six notions of what makes a state conscious can be independently
specified, they are obviously not without potential links, nor do they exhaust
the realm of possible options. Drawing connections, one might argue that states
appear in the stream of consciousness only in so far as we are aware of them,
and thus forge a bond between the first meta-mental notion of a conscious state
and the stream or narrative concept. Or one might connect the access with the
qualitative or phenomenal notions of a conscious state by trying to show that
states that represent in those ways make their contents widely available in the
respect required by the access notion.
Aiming to
go beyond the six options, one might distinguish conscious from nonconscious
states by appeal to aspects of their intra-mental dynamics and interactions
other than mere access relations; e.g., conscious states might manifest a
richer stock of content-sensitive interactions or a greater degree of flexible
purposive guidance of the sort associated with the self-conscious control of
thought. Alternatively, one might try to define conscious states in terms of
conscious creatures. That is, one might give some account of what it is to be a
conscious creature or perhaps even a conscious self, and then define one's
notion of a conscious state in terms of being a state of such a creature or
system, which would be the converse of the last option considered above for
defining conscious creatures in terms of conscious mental states.
2.3 Consciousness
as an entity
The noun
“consciousness” has an equally diverse range of meanings that largely parallel
those of the adjective “conscious”. Distinctions can be drawn between creature
and state consciousness as well as among the varieties of each. One can refer
specifically to phenomenal consciousness, access consciousness, reflexive or
meta-mental consciousness, and narrative consciousness among other varieties.
Here
consciousness itself is not typically treated as a substantive entity but
merely the abstract reification of whatever property or aspect is attributed by
the relevant use of the adjective “conscious”. Access consciousness is just the
property of having the required sort of internal access relations, and
qualitative consciousness is simply the property that is attributed when
“conscious” is applied in the qualitative sense to mental states. How much this
commits one to the ontological status of consciousness per se will depend on
how much of a Platonist one is about universals in general. (See the entry on the
medieval problem of universals.) It need not commit one to
consciousness as a distinct entity any more than one's use of “square”, “red”
or “gentle” commits one to the existence of squareness, redness or gentleness
as distinct entities.
Though it
is not the norm, one could nonetheless take a more robustly realist view of
consciousness as a component of reality. That is one could think of
consciousness as more on a par with electromagnetic fields than with life.
Since the
demise of vitalism, we do not think of life per se as something distinct from living
things. There are living things including organisms, states, properties and
parts of organisms, communities and evolutionary lineages of organisms, but
life is not itself a further thing, an additional component of reality, some
vital force that gets added into living things. We apply the adjectives
“living” and “alive” correctly to many things, and in doing so we might be said
to be attributing life to them but with no meaning or reality other than that
involved in their being living things.
Electromagnetic
fields by contrast are regarded as real and independent parts of our physical
world. Even though one may sometimes be able to specify the values of such a
field by appeal to the behavior of particles in it, the fields themselves are
regarded as concrete constituents of reality and not merely as abstractions or
sets of relations among particles.
Similarly
one could regard “consciousness” as referring to a component or aspect of
reality that manifests itself in conscious states and creatures but is more
than merely the abstract nominalization of the adjective “conscious” we apply
to them. Though such strongly realist views are not very common at present,
they should be included within the logical space of options.
There are
thus many concepts of consciousness, and both “conscious” and “consciousness”
are used in a wide range of ways with no privileged or canonical meaning.
However, this may be less of an embarrassment than an embarrassment of riches.
Consciousness is a complex feature of the world, and understanding it will
require a diversity of conceptual tools for dealing with its many differing
aspects. Conceptual plurality is thus just what one would hope for. As long as
one avoids confusion by being clear about one's meanings, there is great value
in having a variety of concepts by which we can access and grasp consciousness
in all its rich complexity. However, one should not assume that conceptual
plurality implies referential divergence. Our multiple concepts of
consciousness may in fact pick out varying aspects of a single unified
underlying mental phenomenon. Whether and to what extent they do so remains an
open question.
3.
Problems of Consciousness
The task
of understanding consciousness is an equally diverse project. Not only do many
different aspects of mind count as conscious in some sense, each is also open
to various respects in which it might be explained or modeled. Understanding
consciousness involves 'a multiplicity of not only explanation' but also of 'questions
that they pose and the sorts of answers they require'. At the risk of
oversimplifying, the relevant questions can be gathered under three crude
rubrics as the What, How, and Why questions:
- The Descriptive Question: What is
consciousness? What are its principal features? And by what means can they
be best discovered, described and modeled?
- The Explanatory Question: How does
consciousness of the relevant sort come to exist? Is it a primitive aspect
of reality, and if not how does (or could) consciousness in the relevant
respect arise from or be caused by nonconscious entities or processes?
- The Functional Question: Why does
'consciousness of the relevant sort' exist? Does it have a function, and
if so what is it? Does it act causally and if so with what sorts of
effects? Does it make a difference to the operation of systems in which it
is present, and if so why and how?
The three
questions focus respectively on describing the features of consciousness,
explaining its underlying basis or cause, and explicating its role or value.
The divisions among the three are of course somewhat artificial, and in
practice the answers one gives to each will depend in part on what one says
about the others. One cannot, for example, adequately answer the what question
and describe the main features of consciousness without addressing the why
issue of its functional role within systems whose operations it affects. Nor
could one explain how the relevant sort of consciousness might arise from
nonconscious processes unless one had a clear account of just what features had
to be caused or realized to count as producing it. Those caveats
notwithstanding, the three-way division of questions provides a useful
structure for articulating the overall explanatory project and for assessing
the adequacy of particular theories or models of consciousness.
4.
The descriptive question: What are the features of consciousness?
The What question asks us to describe and model
the principal features of consciousness, but just which features are relevant
will vary with the sort of consciousness we aim to capture. The main properties
of access consciousness may be quite unlike those of qualitative or phenomenal
consciousness, and those of reflexive consciousness or narrative consciousness
may differ from both. However, by building up detailed theories of each type,
we may hope to find important links between them and perhaps even to discover that
they coincide in at least some key respects.
4.1
First-person and third-person data
The
general descriptive project will require a variety of investigational methods
(Flanagan 1992). Though one might naively regard the facts of consciousness as
too self-evident to require any systematic methods of gathering data, the
epistemic task is in reality far from trivial (Husserl 1913).
First-person
introspective access provides a rich and essential source of insight into our
conscious mental life, but it is neither sufficient in itself nor even
especially helpful unless used in a trained and disciplined way. Gathering the
needed evidence about the structure of experience requires us both to become
phenomenologically sophisticated self-observers and to complement our
introspective results with many types of third-person data available to
external observers (Searle 1992, Varela 1995, Siewert 1998)
As
phenomenologists have known for more than a century, discovering the structure
of conscious experience demands a rigorous inner-directed stance that is quite
unlike our everyday form of self-awareness (Husserl 1929, Merleau-Ponty 1945).
Skilled observation of the needed sort requires training, effort and the
ability to adopt alternative perspectives on one's experience.
The need
for third-person empirical data gathered by external observers is perhaps most
obvious with regard to the more clearly functional types of consciousness such
as access consciousness, but it is required even with regard to phenomenal and
qualitative consciousness. For example, deficit studies that correlate various
neural and functional sites of damage with abnormalities of conscious
experience can make us aware of aspects of phenomenal structure that escape our
normal introspective awareness. As such case studies show, things can come
apart in experience that seem inseparably unified or singular from our normal
first-person point of view (Sacks 1985, Shallice 1988, Farah 1995).
Or to
pick another example, third-person data can make us aware of how our
experiences of acting and our experiences of event-timing affect each other in
ways that we could never discern through mere introspection (Libet 1985, Wegner
2002). Nor are the facts gathered by these third person methods merely about
the causes or bases of consciousness; they often concern the very structure of
phenomenal consciousness itself. First-person, third-person and perhaps even
second-person (Varela 1995) interactive methods will all be needed to collect
the requisite evidence.
Using all
these sources of data, we will hopefully be able to construct detailed
descriptive models of the various sorts of consciousness. Though the specific
features of most importance may vary among the different types, our overall
descriptive project will need to address at least the following seven general
aspects of consciousness (sections 4.2–4.7).
4.2
Qualitative character
Qualitative
character is often
equated with so called “raw feels” and illustrated by the redness one
experiences when one looks at ripe tomatoes or the specific sweet savor one
encounters when one tastes an equally ripe pineapple (Locke 1688). The relevant
sort of qualitative character is not restricted to sensory states, but is
typically taken to be present as an aspect of experiential states in general,
such as experienced thoughts or desires (Siewert 1998).
The
existence of such feels may seem to some to mark the threshold for states or
creatures that are really conscious. If an organism senses and responds in apt
ways to its world but lacks such qualia, then it might count as conscious at
best in a loose and less than literal sense. Or so at least it would seem to
those who take qualitative consciousness in the “what it is like” sense to be
philosophically and scientifically central (Nagel 1974, Chalmers 1996).
Qualia
problems in many forms—Can there be inverted qualia? (Block 1980a 1980b,
Shoemaker 1981, 1982) Are qualia epiphenomenal? (Jackson 1982, Chalmers 1996)
How could neural states give rise to qualia? (Levine 1983, McGinn 1991)—have
loomed large in the recent past. But the What question raises a more basic
problem of qualia: namely that of giving a clear and articulated description of
our qualia space and the status of specific qualia within it.
Absent
such a model, factual or descriptive errors are all too likely. For example,
claims about the unintelligibility of the link between experienced red and any
possible neural substrate of such an experience sometimes treat the relevant
color quale as a simple and sui generis property (Levine 1983), but phenomenal
redness in fact exists within a complex color space with multiple systematic
dimensions and similarity relations (Hardin 1992). Understanding the specific
color quale relative to that larger relational structure not only gives us a better
descriptive grasp of its qualitative nature, it may also provide some “hooks”
to which one might attach intelligible psycho-physical links.
Color may
be the exception in terms of our having a specific and well developed formal
understanding of the relevant qualitative space, but it is not likely an
exception with regard to the importance of such spaces to our understanding of
qualitative properties in general (Clark 1993, P.M. Churchland 1995). (See the
entry on qualia.)
4.3
Phenomenal structure
Phenomenal
structure should
not be conflated with qualitative structure, despite the sometimes
interchangeable use of “qualia” and “phenomenal properties” in the literature.
“Phenomenal organization” covers all the various kinds of order and structure
found within the domain of experience, i.e., within the domain of the world as
it appears to
us. There are obviously important links between the phenomenal and the
qualitative. Indeed qualia might be best understood as properties of phenomenal
or experienced objects, but there is in fact far more to the phenomenal than
raw feels. As Kant (1787), Husserl (1913), and generations of phenomenologists
have shown, the phenomenal structure of experience is richly intentional and
involves not only sensory ideas and qualities but complex representations of
time, space, cause, body, self, world and the organized structure of lived
reality in all its conceptual and non-conceptual forms.
Since
many non-conscious states also have intentional and representational aspects,
it may be best to consider phenomenal structure as involving a special kind of
intentional and representational organization and content, the kind
distinctively associated with consciousness (Siewert 1998). (See the entry on representational
theories of consciousness).
Answering
the What question requires a careful account of the coherent and densely
organized representational framework within which particular experiences are
embedded. Since most of that structure is only implicit in the organization of
experience, it cannot just be read off by introspection. Articulating the
structure of the phenomenal domain in a clear and intelligible way is a long
and difficult process of inference and model building (Husserl 1929).
Introspection can aid it, but a lot of theory construction and ingenuity are
also needed.
There has
been recent philosophical debate about the range of properties that are
phenomenally present or manifest in conscious experience, in particular with
respect to cognitive states such as believing or thinking. Some have argued for
a so called “thin” view according to which phenomenal properties are limited to
qualia representing basic sensory properties, such as colors, shapes, tones and
feels. According to such theorists, there is no distinctive
“what-it-is-likeness” involved in believing that Paris is the capital of France
or that 17 is a prime number (Tye, Prinz 2012). Some imagery, e.g., of the
Eiffel Tower, may accompany our having such a thought, but that is incidental
to it and the cognitive state itself has no phenomenal feel. On the thin view,
the phenomenal aspect of perceptual states as well is limited to basic sensory
features; when one sees an image of Winston Churchill, one's perceptual
phenomenology is limited only to the spatial aspects of his face.
Others
holds a “thick” view according to which the phenomenology of perception
includes a much wider range of features and cognitive states have a distinctive
phenomenology as well (Strawson 2003, Pitt 2004, Seigel 2010). On the thick
view, the what-it-is-likeness of perceiving an image of Marilyn Monroe includes
one's recognition of her history as part of the felt aspect of the experience,
and beliefs and thoughts as well can and typically do have a distinctive non-sensory
phenomenology. Both sides of the debate are well represented in the volume
Cognitive Phenomenology (Bayne and Montague 2010).
4.4
Subjectivity ***
Subjectivity is another notion sometimes equated with the
qualitative or the phenomenal aspects of consciousness in the literature, but
again there are good reason to recognize it, at least in some of its forms, as
a distinct feature of consciousness—related to the qualitative and the
phenomenal but different from each. In particular, the epistemic form of
subjectivity concerns apparent limits on the knowability or even the
understandability of various facts about conscious experience (Nagel 1974, Van
Gulick 1985, Lycan 1996).
On Thomas
Nagel's (1974) account, facts about what it is like to be a bat are subjective
in the relevant sense because they can be fully understood only from the
bat-type point of view. Only creatures capable of having or undergoing similar
such experiences can understand their what-it's-likeness in the requisite
empathetic sense. Facts about conscious experience can be at best incompletely
understood from an outside third person point of view, such as those associated
with objective physical science. A similar view about the limits of
third-person theory seems to lie behind claims regarding what Frank Jackson's
(1982) hypothetical Mary, the super color scientist, could not understand about
experiencing red because of her own impoverished history of achromatic visual
experience.
Whether
facts about experience are indeed epistemically limited in this way is open to
debate (Lycan 1996), but the claim that understanding consciousness requires
special forms of knowing and access from the inside point of view is
intuitively plausible and has a long history (Locke 1688). Thus any adequate
answer to the What question must address the epistemic status of consciousness,
both our abilities to understand it and their limits (Papineau 2002, Chalmers
2003). (See the entry on self-knowledge).
4.5
Self-perspectival organization
The
perspectival structure of consciousness is one aspect of its overall phenomenal
organization, but it is important enough to merit discussion in its own right.
Insofar as the key perspective is that of the conscious self, the specific
feature might be called self-perspectuality. Conscious experiences do not exist as
isolated mental atoms, but as modes or states of a conscious self or subject
(Descartes 1644, Searle 1992, though pace Hume 1739). A visual experience of a
blue sphere is always a matter of there being some self or subject who is
appeared to in that way. A sharp and stabbing pain is always a pain felt or
experienced by some conscious subject. The self need not appear as an explicit
element in our experiences, but as Kant (1787) noted the “I think” must at
least potentially accompany each of them.
The self
might be taken as the perspectival point from which the world of objects is
present to experience (Wittgenstein 1921). It provides not only a spatial and
temporal perspective for our experience of the world but one of meaning and
intelligibility as well. The intentional coherence of the experiential domain
relies upon the dual interdependence between self and world: the self as
perspective from which objects are known and the world as the integrated
structure of objects and events whose possibilities of being experienced
implicitly define the nature and location of the self (Kant 1787, Husserl
1929).
Conscious
organisms obviously differ in the extent to which they constitute a unified and
coherent self, and they likely differ accordingly in the sort or degree of
perspectival focus they embody in their respective forms of experience (Lorenz
1977). Consciousness may not require a distinct or substantial self of the
traditional Cartesian sort, but at least some degree of perspectivally
self-like organization seems essential for the existence of anything that might
count as conscious experience. Experiences seem no more able to exist without a
self or subject to undergo them than could ocean waves exist without the sea
through which they move. The Descriptive question thus requires some account of
the self-perspectival aspect of experience and the self-like organization of
conscious minds on which it depends, even if the relevant account treats the
self in a relatively deflationary and virtual way (Dennett 1991, 1992).
4.6
Unity
Unity is closely linked with the self-perspective,
but it merits specific mention on its own as a key aspect of the organization
of consciousness. Conscious systems and conscious mental states both involve
many diverse forms of unity. Some are causal unities associated with the integration
of action and control into a unified focus of agency. Others are more
representational and intentional forms of unity involving the integration of
diverse items of content at many scales and levels of binding (Cleeremans
2003).
Some such
integrations are relatively local as when diverse features detected within a
single sense modality are combined into a representation of external objects
bearing those features, e.g. when one has a conscious visual experience of a
moving red soup can passing above a green striped napkin (Triesman and Gelade
1980).
Other
forms of intentional unity encompass a far wider range of contents. The content
of one's present experience of the room in which one sits depends in part upon
its location within a far larger structure associated with one's awareness of
one's existence as an ongoing temporally extended observer within a world of
spatially connected independently existing objects (Kant 1787, Husserl 1913).
The individual experience can have the content that it does only because it
resides within that larger unified structure of representation. (See the entry
on unity of
consciousness.)
Particular
attention has been paid recently to the notion of phenomenal unity (Bayne 2010)
and its relation to other forms of conscious unity such as those involving
representational, functional or neural integration. Some have argued that
phenomenal unity can be reduced to representational unity (Tye 2005) while
others have denied the possibility of any such reduction (Bayne 2010).
4.7
Intentionality and transparency
Conscious
mental states are typically regarded as having a representational or
intentional aspect in so far as they are about things, refer to things or have
satisfaction conditions. One's conscious visual experience correctly
represents the world if there are lilacs in a white vase on the
table (pace Travis 2004), one's conscious memory is of the attack on the World Trade Center,
and one's conscious desire is for a glass of cold water. However,
nonconscious states can also exhibit intentionality in such ways, and it is
important to understand the ways in which the representational aspects of
conscious states resemble and differ from those of nonconscious states
(Carruthers 2000). Searle (1990) offers a contrary view according to which only
conscious states and dispositions to have conscious states can be genuinely
intentional, but most theorists regard intentionality as extending widely into
the unconscious domain. (See the entry on consciousness
and intentionality.)
One
potentially important dimension of difference concerns so called transparency,
which is an important feature of consciousness in two interrelated metaphoric
senses, each of which has an intentional, an experiential and a functional
aspect.
Conscious
perceptual experience is often said to be transparent, or in G.E. Moore's
(1922) phrase “diaphanous”. We transparently “look through” our sensory
experience in so far as we seem directly aware of external objects and events
present to us rather than being aware of any properties of experience by which
it presents or represents such objects to us. When I look out at the wind-blown
meadow, it is the undulating green grass of which I am aware not of any green
property of my visual experience. (See the entry on representational
theories of consciousness.) Moore himself believed we could become
aware of those latter qualities with effort and redirection of attention,
though some contemporary transparency advocates deny it (Harman 1990, Tye 1995,
Kind 2003).
Conscious
thoughts and experiences are also transparent in a semantic sense in that their
meanings seem immediately known to us in the very act of thinking them (Van
Gulick 1992). In that sense we might be said to ‘think right through’ them to
what they mean or represent. Transparency in this semantic sense may correspond
at least partly with what John Searle calls the “intrinsic intentionality” of
consciousness (Searle 1992).
Our
conscious mental states seem to have their meanings intrinsically or from the
inside just by being what they are in themselves, by contrast with many
externalist theories of mental content that ground meaning in causal,
counterfactual or informational relations between bearers of intentionality and
their semantic or referential objects.
The view
of conscious content as intrinsically determined and internally self-evident is
sometimes supported by appeals to brain in the vat intuitions, which make it
seem that the envatted brain's conscious mental states would keep all their
normal intentional contents despite the loss of all their normal causal and
informational links to the world (Horgan and Tienson 2002). There is continued
controversy about such cases and about competing internalist (Searle 1992) and
externalist views (Dretske 1995) of conscious intentionality.
Though semantic
transparency and intrinsic intentionality have some affinities, they should not
be simply equated, since it may be possible to accommodate the former notion
within a more externalist account of content and meaning. Both semantic and
sensory transparency obviously concern the representational or intentional
aspects of consciousness, but they are also experiential aspects of our
conscious life. They are part of what it's like or how it feels phenomenally to
be conscious. They also both have functional aspects, in so far as conscious
experiences interact with each other in richly content-appropriate ways that
manifest our transparent understanding of their contents.
4.8
Dynamic flow
The dynamics of consciousness are evident in the
coherent order of its ever changing process of flow and self-transformation,
what William James (1890) called the “stream of consciousness.”
Some temporal sequences of experience are generated by purely internal factors
as when one thinks through a puzzle, and others depend in part upon external
causes as when one chases a fly ball, but even the latter sequences are shaped
in large part by how consciousness transforms itself.
Whether
partly in response to outer influences or entirely from within, each moment to
moment sequence of experience grows coherently out of those that preceded it,
constrained and enabled by the global structure of links and limits embodied in
its underlying prior organization (Husserl 1913). In that respect,
consciousness is an autopoietic system, i.e., a self-creating and
self-organizing system (Varela and Maturana 1980).
As a
conscious mental agent I can do many things such as scan my room, scan a mental
image of it, review in memory the courses of a recent restaurant meal along
with many of its tastes and scents, reason my way through a complex problem, or
plan a grocery shopping trip and execute that plan when I arrive at the market.
These are all routine and common activities, but each involves the directed
generation of experiences in ways that manifest an implicit practical
understanding of their intentional properties and interconnected contents (Van
Gulick 2000).
Consciousness
is a dynamic process, and thus an adequate descriptive answer to the What
question must deal with more than just its static or momentary properties. In
particular, it must give some account of the temporal dynamics of consciousness
and the ways in which its self-transforming flow reflects both its intentional
coherence and the semantic self-understanding embodied in the organized
controls through which conscious minds continually remake themselves as
autopoietic systems engaged with their worlds.
A
comprehensive descriptive account of consciousness would need to deal with more
than just these seven features, but having a clear account of each of them
would take us a long way toward answering the “What is consciousness?”
question.
5.
The explanatory question: How can consciousness exist?
The How question focuses on explanation rather
than description. It asks us to explain the basic status of consciousness and
its place in nature. Is it a fundamental feature of reality in its own right,
or does its existence depend upon other nonconscious items, be they physical,
biological, neural or computational? And if the latter, can we explain or
understand how the relevant nonconscious items could cause or realize
consciousness? Put simply, can we explain how to make something conscious out
of things that are not conscious?
5.1
Diversity of explanatory projects
The How
question is not a single question, but rather a general family of more specific
questions (Van Gulick 1995). They all concern the possibility of explaining
some sort or aspect of consciousness, but they vary in their particular
explananda, the restrictions on their explanans, and their criteria for
successful explanation. For example, one might ask whether we can explain
access consciousness computationally by mimicking the requisite access
relations in a computational model. Or one might be concerned instead with
whether the phenomenal and qualitative properties of a conscious creature's
mind can be a priori deduced from a description of the
neural properties of its brain processes. Both are versions of the How
question, but they ask about the prospects of very different explanatory
projects, and thus may differ in their answers (Lycan 1996). It would be
impractical, if not impossible, to catalog all the possible versions of the How
question, but some of the main options can be listed.
Explananda. Possible explananda would include the various
sorts of state and creature consciousness distinguished above, as well as the
seven features of consciousness listed in response to the What question. Those
two types of explananda overlap and intersect. We might for example aim to
explain the dynamic aspect either of phenomenal or of access consciousness. Or
we could try to explain the subjectivity of either qualitative or meta-mental
consciousness. Not every feature applies to every sort of consciousness, but
all apply to several. How one explains a given feature in relation to one sort
of consciousness may not correspond with what is needed to explain it relative
to another.
Explanans. The range of possible explanans is also
diverse. In perhaps its broadest form, the How question asks how consciousness
of the relevant sort could be caused or realized by nonconscious items, but we
can generate a wealth of more specific questions by further restricting the
range of the relevant explanans. One might seek to explain how a given feature
of consciousness is caused or realized by underlying neural processes, biological structures,physical mechanisms, functional or teleofunctional relations, computational organization, or even by nonconscious
mental states. The
prospects for explanatory success will vary accordingly. In general the more
limited and elementary the range of the explanans, the more difficult the
problem of explaining how could it suffice to produce consciousness (Van Gulick
1995).
Criteria
of explanation. The third
key parameter is how one defines the criterion for a successful explanation.
One might require that the explanandum be a priori deducible from the explanans, although
it is controversial whether this is either a necessary or a sufficient
criterion for explaining consciousness (Jackson 1993). Its sufficiency will
depend in part on the nature of the premises from which the deduction proceeds.
As a matter of logic, one will need some bridge principles to connect
propositions or sentences about consciousness with those that do not mention
it. If one's premises concern physical or neural facts, then one will need some
bridge principles or links that connect such facts with facts about
consciousness (Kim 1998). Brute links, whether nomic or merely well confirmed
correlations, could provide a logically sufficient bridge to infer conclusions
about consciousness. But they would probably not allow us to see how or why
those connections hold, and thus they would fall short of fully explaining how
consciousness exists (Levine 1983, 1993, McGinn 1991).
One could
legitimately ask for more, in particular for some account that made
intelligible why those links hold and perhaps why they could not fail to do so.
A familiar two-stage model for explaining macro-properties in terms of
micro-substrates is often invoked. In the first step, one analyzes the
macro-property in terms of functional conditions, and then in the second stage
one shows that the micro-structures obeying the laws of their own level
nomically suffice to guarantee the satisfaction of the relevant functional
conditions (Armstrong 1968, Lewis 1972).
The
micro-properties of collections of H2O molecules at 20°C suffice to satisfy the
conditions for the liquidity of the water they compose. Moreover, the model
makes intelligible how the liquidity is produced by the micro-properties. A
satisfactory explanation of how consciousness is produced might seem to require
a similar two stage story. Without it, even a priori deducibility might seem explanatorily
less than sufficient, though the need for such a story remains a matter of
controversy (Block and Stalnaker 1999, Chalmers and Jackson 2001).
5.2
The explanatory gap
Our
current inability to supply a suitably intelligible link is sometimes
described, following Joseph Levine (1983), as the existence of an explanatory
gap, and as indicating our incomplete understanding of how
consciousness might depend upon a nonconscious substrate, especially a physical
substrate. The basic gap claim admits of many variations in generality and thus
in strength.
In perhaps
its weakest form, it asserts a practical limit on our present explanatory abilities; given our
current theories and models we can not now articulate an intelligible link. A
stronger version makes an in principle claim about our human
capacities and thus
asserts that given our human cognitive limits we will never be able to bridge
the gap. To us, or creatures cognitively like us, it must remain a residual
mystery (McGinn 1991). Colin McGinn (1995) has argued that given the inherently
spatial nature of both our human perceptual concepts and the scientific
concepts we derive from them, we humans are not conceptually suited for
understanding the nature of the psychophysical link. Facts about that link are
as cognitively closed to us as are facts about multiplication or square roots
to armadillos. They do not fall within our conceptual and cognitive repertoire.
An even stronger version of the gap claim removes the restriction to our
cognitive nature and denies in principle that the gap can be closed by any
cognitive agents.
Those who
assert gap claims disagree among themselves about what metaphysical
conclusions, if any, follow from our supposed epistemic limits. Levine himself
has been reluctant to draw any anti-physicalist ontological conclusions (Levine
1993, 2001). On the other hand some neodualists have tried to use the existence
of the gap to refute physicalism (Foster 1996, Chalmers 1996). The stronger
one's epistemological premise, the better the hope of deriving a metaphysical
conclusion. Thus unsurprisingly, dualist conclusions are often supported by
appeals to the supposed impossibility in principle of closing the gap.
If one
could see on a priori grounds that there is no way in which
consciousness could be intelligibly explained as arising from the physical, it
would not be a big step to concluding that it in fact does not do so (Chalmers
1996). However, the very strength of such an epistemological claim makes it
difficult to assume with begging the metaphysical result in question. Thus
those who wish to use a strong in principle gap claim to refute physicalism must
find independent grounds to support it. Some have appealed to conceivability
arguments for support, such as the alleged conceivability of zombies
molecularly identical with conscious humans but devoid of all phenomenal
consciousness (Campbell 1970, Kirk 1974, Chalmers 1996). Other supporting
arguments invoke the supposed non-functional nature of consciousness and thus
its alleged resistance to the standard scientific method of explaining complex
properties (e.g., genetic dominance) in terms of physically realized functional
conditions (Block 1980a, Chalmers 1996). Such arguments avoid begging the
anti-physicalist question, but they themselves rely upon claims and intuitions
that are controversial and not completely independent of one's basic view about
physicalism. Discussion on the topic remains active and ongoing.
Our
present inability to see any way of closing the gap may exert some pull on our
intuitions, but it may simply reflect the limits of our current theorizing
rather than an unbridgeable in principle barrier (Dennett 1991). Moreover, some
physicalists have argued that explanatory gaps are to be expected and are even
entailed by plausible versions of ontological physicalism, ones that treat
human agents as physically realized cognitive systems with inherent limits that
derive from their evolutionary origin and situated contextual mode of
understanding (Van Gulick 1985, 2003; McGinn 1991, Papineau 1995, 2002). On
this view, rather than refuting physicalism, the existence of explanatory gaps
may confirm it. Discussion and disagreement on these topics remains active and
ongoing.
5.3
Reductive and non-reductive explanation
As the
need for intelligible linkage has shown, a priori deducibility is not in itself
obviously sufficient for successful explanation (Kim 1980), nor is it clearly
necessary. Some weaker logical link might suffice in many explanatory contexts.
We can sometimes tell enough of a story about how facts of one sort depend upon
those of another to satisfy ourselves that the latter do in fact cause or
realize the former even if we can not strictly deduce all the former facts from
the latter.
Strict
intertheoretical deduction was taken as the reductive norm by the logical
empiricist account of the unity of science (Putnam and Oppenheim 1958), but in
more recent decades a looser nonreductive picture of relations among the
various sciences has gained favor. In particular, nonreductive materialists
have argued for the so called “autonomy of the special sciences” (Fodor 1974)
and for the view that understanding the natural world requires us to use a
diversity of conceptual and representational systems that may not be strictly
intertranslatable or capable of being put into the tight correspondence
required by the older deductive paradigm of interlevel relations (Putnam 1975).
Economics
is often cited as an example (Fodor 1974, Searle 1992). Economic facts may be
realized by underlying physical processes, but no one seriously demands that we
be able to deduce the relevant economic facts from detailed descriptions of
their underlying physical bases or that we be able to put the concepts and
vocabulary of economics in tight correspondence with those of the physical
sciences.
Nonetheless
our deductive inability is not seen as cause for ontological misgivings; there
is no “money-matter” problem. All that we require is some general and less than
deductive understanding of how economic properties and relations might be
underlain by physical ones. Thus one might opt for a similar criterion for
interpreting the How question and for what counts as explaining how
consciousness might be caused or realized by nonconscious items. However, some
critics, such as Kim (1987), have challenged the coherence of any view that
aims to be both non-reductive and physicalist, though supporters of such views
have replied in turn (Van Gulick 1993).
Others
have argued that consciousness is especially resistant to explanation in
physical terms because of the inherent differences between our subjective and
objective modes of understanding. Thomas Nagel famously argued (1974) that
there are unavoidable limits placed on our ability to understand the
phenomenology of bat experience by our inability to empathetically take on an
experiential perspective like that which characterizes the bat's echo-locatory
auditory experience of its world. Given our inability to undergo similar
experience, we can have at best partial understanding of the nature of such
experience. No amount of knowledge gleaned from the external objective
third-person perspective of the natural sciences will supposedly suffice to
allow us to understand what the bat can understand of its own experience from
its internal first-person subjective point of view.
5.4 Prospects
of explanatory success
The How
question thus subdivides into a diverse family of more specific questions
depending upon the specific sort or feature of consciousness one aims to
explain, the specific restrictions one places on the range of the explanans and
the criterion one uses to define explanatory success. Some of the resulting
variants seem easier to answer than others. Progress may seem likely on some of
the so called “easy problems” of consciousness, such as explaining the dynamics
of access consciousness in terms of the functional or computational
organization of the brain (Baars 1988). Others may seem less tractable,
especially the so-called “hard problem” (Chalmers 1995) which is more or less
that of giving an intelligible account that lets us see in an intuitively
satisfying way how phenomenal or “what it's like” consciousness might arise
from physical or neural processes in the brain.
Positive
answers to some versions of the How questions seem near at hand, but others
appear to remain deeply baffling. Nor should we assume that every version has a
positive answer. If dualism is true, then consciousness in at least some of its
types may be basic and fundamental. If so,we will not be able to explain how it
arises from nonconscious items since it simply does not do so.
One's
view of the prospects for explaining consciousness will typically depend upon
one's perspective. Optimistic physicalists will likely see current explanatory
lapses as merely the reflection of the early stage of inquiry and sure to be
remedied in the not too distant future (Dennett 1991, Searle 1992, P.
M.Churchland 1995). To dualists, those same impasses will signify the
bankruptcy of the physicalist program and the need to recognize consciousness
as a fundamental constituent of reality in its own right (Robinson 1982, Foster
1989, 1996, Chalmers 1996). What one sees depends in part on where one stands,
and the ongoing project of explaining consciousness will be accompanied by
continuing debate about its status and prospects for success.
6.
The functional question: Why does consciousness exist?
The
functional or Why question asks about the value or role or consciousness and thus indirectly
about its origin. Does it have a function, and if so what is
it? Does it make a difference to the operation of systems in which it is
present, and if so why and how? If consciousness exists as a complex feature of
biological systems, then its adaptive value is likely relevant to explaining
its evolutionary origin, though of course its present function, if it has one,
need not be the same as that it may have had when it first arose. Adaptive
functions often change over biological time. Questions about the value of
consciousness also have amoral dimension in at least two ways. We are
inclined to regard an organism's moral status as at least partly determined by
the nature and extent to which it is conscious, and conscious states,
especially conscious affective states such as pleasures and pains, play a major
role in many of the accounts of value that underlie moral theory (Singer 1975).
As with
the What and How questions, the Why question poses a general problem that
subdivides into a diversity of more specific inquiries. In so far as the
various sorts of consciousness, e.g., access, phenomenal, meta-mental, are
distinct and separable—which remains an open question—they likely also differ
in their specific roles and values. Thus the Why question may well not have a
single or uniform answer.
6.1
Causal status of consciousness
Perhaps
the most basic issue posed by any version of the Why question is whether or not
consciousness of the relevant sort has any causal impact at all. If it has no
effects and makes no causal difference whatsoever, then it would seem unable to
play any significant role in the systems or organisms in which it is present,
thus undercutting at the outset most inquiries about its possible value. Nor
can the threat of epiphenomenal irrelevance be simply dismissed as an obvious
non-option, since at least some forms of consciousness have been seriously
alleged in the recent literature to lack causal status. (See the entry on epiphenomenalism.) Such
worries have been raised especially with regard to qualia and qualitative
consciousness (Huxley 1874, Jackson 1982, Chalmers 1996), but challenges have
also been leveled against the causal status of other sorts including
meta-mental consciousness (Velmans 1991).
Both
metaphysical and empirical arguments have been given in support of such claims.
Among the former are those that appeal to intuitions about the conceivability
and logical possibility of zombies, i.e., of beings whose behavior, functional
organization, and physical structure down to the molecular level are identical
to those of normal human agents but who lack any qualia or qualitative
consciousness. Some (Kirk 1970, Chalmers 1996) assert such beings are possible
in worlds that share all our physical laws, but others deny it (Dennett 1991,
Levine 2001). If they are possible in such worlds, then it would seem to follow
that even in our world, qualia do not affect the course of physical events
including those that constitute our human behaviors. If those events unfold in
the same way whether or not qualia are present, then qualia appear to be inert
or epiphenomenal at least with respect to events in the physical world.
However, such arguments and the zombie intuitions on which they rely are
controversial and their soundness remains in dispute (Searle 1992, Yablo 1998,
Balog 1999).
Arguments
of a far more empirical sort have challenged the causal status of meta-mental
consciousness, at least in so far as its presence can be measured by the
ability to report on one's mental state. Scientific evidence is claimed to show
that consciousness of that sort is neither necessary for any type of mental
ability nor does it occur early enough to act as a cause of the acts or
processes typically thought to be its effects (Velmans 1991). According to
those who make such arguments, the sorts of mental abilities that are typically
thought to require consciousness can all be realized unconsciously in the
absence of the supposedly required self-awareness.
Moreover,
even when conscious self-awareness is present, it allegedly occurs too late to
be the cause of the relevant actions rather than their result or at best a
joint effect of some shared prior cause (Libet 1985). Self-awareness or
meta-mental consciousness according to these arguments turns out to be a
psychological after-effect rather than an initiating cause, more like a post
facto printout or the
result displayed on one's computer screen than like the actual processor
operations that produce both the computer's response and its display.
Once
again the arguments are controversial, and both the supposed data and their
interpretation are subjects of lively disagreement (see Flanagan 1992, and
commentaries accompanying Velmans 1991). Though the empirical arguments, like
the zombie claims, require one to consider seriously whether some forms of
consciousness may be less causally potent than is typically assumed, many
theorists regard the empirical data as no real threat to the causal status of
consciousness.
If the
epiphenomenalists are wrong and consciousness, in its various forms, is indeed
causal, what sorts of effects does it have and what differences does it make?
How do mental processes that involve the relevant sort of consciousness differ
form those that lack it? What function(s) might consciousness play? The
following six sections (6.2–6.7) discuss some of the more commonly given
answers. Though the various functions overlap to some degree, each is distinct,
and they differ as well in the sorts of consciousness with which each is most
aptly linked.
6.2
Flexible control
Increased
flexibility and sophistication of control. Conscious mental processes appear to provide
highly flexible and adaptive forms of control. Though unconscious automatic
processes can be extremely efficient and rapid, they typically operate in ways
that are more fixed and predetermined than those which involve conscious
self-awareness (Anderson 1983). Conscious awareness is thus of most importance
when one is dealing with novel situations and previously unencountered problems
or demands (Penfield 1975, Armstrong 1981).
Standard
accounts of skill acquisition stress the importance of conscious awareness
during the initial learning phase, which gradually gives way to more automatic
processes of the sort that require little attention or conscious oversight
(Schneider and Shiffrin 1977). Conscious processing allows for the construction
or compilation of specifically tailored routines out of elementary units as
well as for the deliberate control of their execution.
There is
a familiar tradeoff between flexibility and speed; controlled conscious
processes purchase their customized versatility at the price of being slow and
effortful in contrast to the fluid rapidity of automatic unconscious mental
operations (Anderson 1983). The relevant increases in flexibility would seem most
closely connected with the meta-mental or higher-order form of consciousness in
so far as the enhanced ability to control processes depends upon greater
self-awareness. However, flexibility and sophisticated modes of control may be
associated as well with the phenomenal and access forms of consciousness.
6.3
Social coordination
Enhanced
capacity for social coordination. Consciousness
of the meta-mental sort may well involve not only an increase in self-awareness
but also an enhanced understanding of the mental states of other minded
creatures, especially those of other members of one's social group (Humphreys
1982). Creatures that are conscious in the relevant meta-mental sense not only
have beliefs, motives, perceptions and intentions but understand what it is to
have such states and are aware of both themselves and others as having them.
This
increase in mutually shared knowledge of each other's minds, enables the
relevant organisms to interact, cooperate and communicate in more advanced and
adaptive ways. Although meta-mental consciousness is the sort most obviously
linked to such a socially coordinative role, narrative consciousness of the
kind associated with the stream of consciousness is also clearly relevant in so
far as it involves the application to one's own case of the interpretative
abilities that derive in part from their social application (Ryle 1949, Dennett
1978, 1992).
6.4
Integrated representation
More
unified and densely integrated representation of reality.
Conscious experience presents us with a world of objects independently existing
in space and time. Those objects are typically present to us in a multi-modal
fashion that involves the integration of information from various sensory
channels as well as from background knowledge and memory. Conscious experience
presents us not with isolated properties or features but with objects and
events situated in an ongoing independent world, and it does so by embodying in
its experiential organization and dynamics the dense network of relations and interconnections
that collectively constitute the meaningful structure of a world of objects
(Kant 1787, Husserl 1913, Campbell 1997).
Of
course, not all sensory information need be experienced to have an adaptive
effect on behavior. Adaptive non-experiential sensory-motor links can be found
both in simple organisms, as well as in some of the more direct and reflexive
processes of higher organisms. But when experience is present, it provides a
more unified and integrated representation of reality, one that typically
allows for more open-ended avenues of response (Lorenz 1977). Consider for
example the representation of space in an organism whose sensory input channels
are simply linked to movement or to the orientation of a few fixed mechanisms
such as those for feeding or grabbing prey, and compare it with that in an
organism capable of using its spatial information for flexible navigation of
its environment and for whatever other spatially relevant aims or goals it may
have, as when a person visually scans her office or her kitchen (Gallistel
1990).
It is
representation of this latter sort that is typically made available by the
integrated mode of presentation associated with conscious experience. The unity
of experienced space is just one example of the sort of integration associated
with our conscious awareness of an objective world. (See the entry on unity of
consciousness.)
This
integrative role or value is most directly associated with access
consciousness, but also clearly with the larger phenomenal and intentional
structure of experience. It is relevant even to the qualitative aspect of
consciousness in so far as qualia play an important role in our experience of
unified objects in a unified space or scene. It is intimately tied as well to
the transparency of experience described in response to the What question,
especially to semantic transparency (Van Gulick 1993). Integration of
information plays a major role in several current neuro-cognitive theories of
consciousness especially Global Workspace theories (see section 9.5) and Giulio
Tononi's Integrated Information theory. (section 9.6 below).
6.5
Informational access
More
global informational access. The information carried in conscious
mental states is typically available for use by a diversity of mental
subsystems and for application to a wide range of potential situations and
actions (Baars 1988). Nonconscious information is more likely to be
encapsulated within particular mental modules and available for use only with
respect to the applications directly connected to that subsystem's operation
(Fodor 1983). Making information conscious typically widens the sphere of its
influence and the range of ways it which it can be used to adaptively guide or
shape both inner and outer behavior. A state's being conscious may be in part a
matter of what Dennett calls “cerebral celebrity”, i.e., of its ability to have
a content-appropriate impact on other mental states.
This
particular role is most directly and definitionally tied to the notion of
access consciousness (Block 1995), but meta-mental consciousness as well as the
phenomenal and qualitative forms all seem plausibly linked to such increases in
the availability of information (Armstrong 1981, Tye 1985). Diverse cognitive
and neuro-cognitive theories incorporate access as a central feature of
consciousness and conscious processing. Global Workspace theories, Prinz's
Attendend Intermediate Representation (AIR) (Prinz 2012) and Tononi's Integrated
Information Theory (IIT) all distinguish conscious states and processes at
least partly in terms of enhanced wide spread access to the state's content
(See section 9.6)
6.6
Freedom of will
Increased
freedom of choice or free will. The issue of free will remains
a perennial philosophical problem, not only with regard to whether or not it
exists but even as to what it might or should consist in (Dennett 1984, van
Inwagen 1983, Hasker 1999, Wegner 2002). (See the entry on free will.) The
notion of free will may itself remain too murky and contentious to shed any
clear light on the role of consciousness, but there is a traditional intuition
that the two are deeply linked.
Consciousness
has been thought to open a realm of possibilities, a sphere of options within
which the conscious self might choose or act freely. At a minimum,
consciousness might seem a necessary precondition for any such freedom or
self-determination (Hasker 1999). How could one engage in the requisite sort of
free choice, while remaining solely within the unconscious domain? How can one
determine one's own will without being conscious of it and of the options one
has to shape it.
The
freedom to chose one's actions and the ability to determine one's own nature
and future development may admit of many interesting variations and degrees
rather than being a simple all or nothing matter, and various forms or levels
of consciousness might be correlated with corresponding degrees or types of
freedom and self-determination (Dennett 1984, 2003). The link with freedom
seems strongest for the meta-mental form of consciousness given its emphasis on
self-awareness, but potential connections also seem possible for most of the
other sorts as well.
6.7
Intrinsic motivation
Intrinsically
motivating states. At least some conscious states appear to have the motive force
they do intrinsically. In particular, the functional and motivational roles of
conscious affective states, such as pleasures and pains, seem intrinsic to
their experiential character and inseparable from their qualitative and
phenomenal properties, though the view has been challenged (Nelkin 1989,
Rosenthal 1991). The attractive positive motivational aspect of a pleasure
seems a part of its directly experienced phenomenal feel, as does the negative
affective character of a pain, at least in the case of normal non-pathological
experience.
There is
considerable disagreement about the extent to which the feel and motive force
of pain can dissociate in abnormal cases, and some have denied the existence of
such intrinsically motivating aspects altogether (Dennett 1991). However, at
least in the normal case, the negative motivational force of pain seems built right into the feel of the experience
itself.
Just how this might be so remains less than
clear, and perhaps the appearance of intrinsic and directly experienced
motivational force is illusory. But if it is real, then it may be one of the
most important and evolutionarily oldest respects in which consciousness makes
a difference to the mental systems and processes in which it is present
(Humphreys 1992).
Other
suggestions have been made about the possible roles and value of consciousness,
and these six surely do not exhaust the options. Nonetheless, they are among
the most prominent recent hypotheses, and they provide a fair survey of the
sorts of answers that have been offered to the Why question by those who
believe consciousness does indeed make a difference.
6.8
Constitutive and contingent roles
One
further point requires clarification about the various respects in which the
proposed functions might answer the Why question. In particular one should
distinguish between constitutive cases and cases of contingent
realization. In the former, fulfilling the role constitutes being
conscious in the relevant sense, while in the latter case consciousness of a
given sort is just one way among several in which the requisite role might be
realized (Van Gulick 1993).
For
example, making information globally available for use by a wide variety of
subsystems and behavioral applications may constitute its being conscious in
the access sense. By contrast, even if the qualitative and phenomenal forms of
consciousness involve a highly unified and densely integrated representation of
objective reality, it may be possible to produce representations having those
functional characteristics but which are not qualitative or phenomenal in
nature.
The fact
that in us the
modes of representation with those characteristics also have qualitative and
phenomenal properties may reflect contingent historical facts about the
particular design solution that happened to arise in our evolutionary ancestry.
If so, there may be quite other means of achieving a comparable result without
qualitative or phenomenal consciousness. Whether this is the right way to think
about phenomenal and qualitative conscious is unclear; perhaps the tie to
unified and densely integrated representation is in fact as intimate and
constitutive as it seems to be in the case of access consciousness (Carruthers
2000). Regardless of how that issue gets resolved, it is important to not to
conflate constitution accounts with contingent realization accounts when
addressing the function of consciousness and answering the question of why it
exists (Chalmers 1996).
7.
Theories of consciousness
In
response to the What, How and Why questions many theories of consciousness have
been proposed in recent years. However, not all theories of consciousness are
theories of the same thing. They vary not only in the specific sorts of
consciousness they take as their object, but also in their theoretical aims.
Perhaps
the largest division is between general metaphysical theories that aim to
locate consciousness in the overall ontological scheme of reality and more
specific theories that offer detailed accounts of its nature, features and
role. The line between the two sorts of theories blurs a bit, especially in so
far as many specific theories carry at least some implicit commitments on the
more general metaphysical issues. Nonetheless, it is useful to keep the
division in mind when surveying the range of current theoretical offerings.
8.
Metaphysical theories of consciousness
General
metaphysical theories offer answers to the conscious version of the mind-body
problem, “What is the ontological status of consciousness relative to the world
of physical reality?” The available responses largely parallel the standard
mind-body options including the main versions of dualism and physicalism.
8.1
Dualist theories
Dualist
theories regard at
least some aspects of consciousness as falling outside the realm of the
physical,but specific forms of dualism differ in just which aspects those are.
(See the entry on dualism.)
Substance
dualism, such as traditional Cartesian dualism (Descartes 1644),
asserts the existence of both physical and non-physical substances. Such
theories entail the existence of non-physical minds or selves as entities in
which consciousness inheres. Though substance dualism is at present largely out
of favor, it does have some contemporary proponents (Swinburne 1986, Foster
1989, 1996).
Property
dualism in its
several versions enjoys a greater level of current support. All such theories
assert the existence of conscious properties that are neither identical with
nor reducible to physical properties but which may nonetheless be instantiated
by the very same things that instantiate physical properties. In that respect
they might be classified as dual aspect theories. They take some parts of
reality—organisms, brains, neural states or processes—to instantiate properties
of two distinct and disjoint sorts: physical ones and conscious, phenomenal or
qualitative ones. Dual aspect or property dualist theories can be of at least
three different types.
Fundamental
property dualism regards
conscious mental properties as basic constituents of reality on a par with
fundamental physical properties such as electromagnetic charge. They may
interact in causal and law-like ways with other fundamental properties such as
those of physics, but ontologically their existence is not dependent upon nor
derivative from any other properties (Chalmers 1996).
Emergent
property dualism treats
conscious properties as arising from complex organizations of physical
constituents but as doing so in a radical way such that the emergent result is
something over and above its physical causes and is not a
priori predictable
from nor explicable in terms of their strictly physical natures. The coherence
of such emergent views has been challenged (Kim 1998) but they have supporters
(Hasker 1999).
Neutral
monist property dualism treats
both conscious mental properties and physical properties as in some way dependent
upon and derivative from a more basic level of reality, that in itself is
neither mental nor physical (Russell 1927, Strawson 1994). However, if one
takes dualism to be a claim about there being two distinct realms of
fundamental entities or properties, then perhaps neutral monism should not be
classified as a version of property dualism in so far as it does not regard
either mental or physical properties as ultimate or fundamental.
Panpsychism might be regarded as a fourth type of
property dualism in that it regards all the constituents of reality as having
some psychic, or at least proto-psychic, properties distinct from whatever
physical properties they may have (Nagel 1979). Indeed neutral monism might be
consistently combined with some version of panprotopsychism (Chalmers 1996) according to which the
proto-mental aspects of micro-constituents can give rise under suitable
conditions of combination to full blown consciousness. (See the entry on panpsychism.)
The
nature of the relevant proto-psychic aspect remains unclear, and such theories
face a dilemma if offered in hope of answering the Hard Problem. Either the
proto-psychic properties involve the sort of qualitative phenomenal feel that
generates the Hard Problem or they do not. If they do, it is difficult to
understand how they could possibly occur as ubiquitous properties of reality.
How could an electron or a quark have any such experiential feel? However, if
the proto-psychic properties do not involve any such feel, it is not clear how
they are any better able than physical properties to account for qualitative
consciousness in solving the Hard Problem.
A more
modest form of panpsychism has been advocated by the neuroscientist Giulio
Tononi (2008) and endorsed by other neuroscientists including Christof Koch
(2012). This version derives from Tononi's integrated information theory (IIT)
of consciousness that identifies consciousness with integrated information
which can exist in many degrees (see section 9.6 below). According to IIT, even
a simple indicator device such as a single photo diode possesses some degree of
integrated information and thus some limited degree of consciousness, a
consequence which both Tononi and Koch embrace as a form of panpsychism.
A variety
of arguments have been given in favor of dualist and other anti-physicalist
theories of consciousness. Some are largelya
priori in nature such
as those that appeal to the supposed conceivability of zombies (Kirk 1970, Chalmers
1996) or versions of the knowledge argument (Jackson 1982, 1986) which aim to
reach an anti-physicalist conclusion about the ontology of consciousness from
the apparent limits on our ability to fully understand the qualitative aspects
of conscious experience through third-person physical accounts of the brain
processes. (See Jackson 1998, 2004 for a contrary view; see also entries on Zombies, and Qualia:
The Knowledge Argument) Other arguments for dualism are made on
more empirical grounds, such as those that appeal to supposed causal gaps in
the chains of physical causation in the brain (Eccles and Popper 1977) or those
based on alleged anomalies in the temporal order of conscious awareness (Libet
1982, 1985). Dualist arguments of both sorts have been much disputed by
physicalists (P.S. Churchland 1981, Dennett and Kinsbourne 1992).
8.2
Physicalist theories
Most
other metaphysical theories of consciousness are versions of physicalism of one
familiar sort or another.
Eliminativist theories reductively deny the existence of
consciousness or at least the existence of some of its commonly accepted sorts
or features. (See the entry on eliminative
materialism.) The radical eliminativists reject the very notion of consciousness
as muddled or wrongheaded and claim that the conscious/nonconscious distinction
fails to cut mental reality at its joints (Wilkes 1984, 1988). They regard the
idea of consciousness as sufficiently off target to merit elimination and
replacement by other concepts and distinctions more reflective of the true
nature of mind (P. S. Churchland 1983).
Most
eliminativists are more qualified in their negative assessment. Rather than
rejecting the notion outright, they take issue only with some of the prominent
features that it is commonly thought to involve, such as qualia (Dennett 1990,
Carruthers 2000), the conscious self - (Dennett 1992), or the so called
“Cartesian Theater” where the temporal sequence of conscious experience gets
internally projected (Dennett and Kinsbourne 1992). More modest eliminativists,
like Dennett, thus typically combine their qualified denials with a positive
theory of those aspects of consciousness they take as real, such as the
Multiple Drafts Model (section 9.3 below).
Identity
theory, at least strict psycho-physical type-type identity theory,
offers another strongly reductive option by identifying conscious mental
properties, states and processes with physical ones, most typically of a neural
or neurophysiological nature. If having a qualitative conscious experience of
phenomenal red just is being in a brain state with the
relevant neurophysiological properties, then such experiential properties are
real but their reality is a straight forwardly physical reality.
Type-type
identity theory is so
called because it identifies mental and physical types or properties on a par
with identifying the property of being water with the property of being
composed of H2O molecules. After a brief period of popularity in the
early days of contemporary physicalism during the 1950s and 60s (Place 1956,
Smart 1959) it has been far less widely held because of problems such as the
multiple realization objection according to which mental properties are more
abstract and thus capable of being realized by many diverse underlying
structural or chemical substrates (Fodor 1974, Hellman and Thompson 1975). If
one and the same conscious property can be realized by different
neurophysiological (or even non-neurophysiological) properties in different
organisms, then the two properties cannot be strictly identical.
Nonetheless
the type-type identity theory has enjoyed a recent if modest resurgence at
least with respect to qualia or qualitative conscious properties. This has been
in part because treating the relevant psycho-physical link as an identity is
thought by some to offer a way of dissolving the explanatory gap problem (Hill
and McLaughlin 1998, Papineau 1995, 2003). They argue that if the conscious
qualitative property and the neural property are identical, then there is no
need to explain how the latter causes or gives rise to the former. It does not cause it, it is it. And thus there is no gap to
bridge, and no further explanation is needed. Identities are not the sort of
thing that can be explained, since nothing is identical with anything but
itself, and it makes no sense to ask why something is identical with itself.
However,
others contend that the appeal to type-type identity does not so obviously void
the need for explanation (Levine 2001). Even if two descriptions or concepts in
fact refer to one and the same property, one may still reasonably expect some
explanation of that convergence, some account of how they pick out one and the
same thing despite not initially or intuitively seeming to do so. In other cases
of empirically discovered property identities, such as that of heat and kinetic
energy, there is a story to be told that explains the co-referential
convergence, and it seems fair to expect the same in the psycho-physical case.
Thus appealing to type-type identities may not in itself suffice to dissolve
the explanatory gap problem.
Most
physicalist theories of consciousness are neither eliminativist nor based on
strict type-type identities. They acknowledge the reality of consciousness but
aim to locate it within the physical world on the basis of some psycho-physical
relation short of strict property identity.
Among the
common variants are those that take conscious reality to supervene on the physical, be composed
of the physical, or
be realized by the
physical.
Functionalist theories in particular rely heavily on the
notion of realization to explicate the relation between
consciousness and the physical. According to functionalism, a state or process
counts as being of a given mental or conscious type in virtue of the functional
role it plays within a suitably organized system (Block 1980a). A given
physical state realizes the relevant conscious mental type by playing the
appropriate role within the larger physical system that contains it. (See the
entry on functionalism.) The
functionalist often appeals to analogies with other inter-level relations, as
between the biological and biochemical or the chemical and the atomic. In each
case properties or facts at one level are realized by complex interactions
between items at an underlying level.
Critics
of functionalism often deny that consciousness can be adequately explicated in
functional terms (Block 1980a, 1980b, Levine 1983, Chalmers 1996). According to
such critics, consciousness may have interesting functional characteristics but
its nature is not essentially functional. Such claims are sometimes supported
by appeal to the supposed possibility of absent or inverted qualia, i.e., the
possibility of beings who are functionally equivalent to normal humans but who
have reversed qualia or none at all. The status of such possibilities is
controversial (Shoemaker 1981, Dennett 1990, Carruthers 2000), but if accepted
they would seem to pose a problem for the functionalist. (See the entry on qualia.)
Those who
ground ontological physicalism on the realization relation often combine it
with a nonreductive view at the conceptual or representational level that
stresses the autonomy of the special sciences and the distinct modes of
description and cognitive access they provide.
Non-reductive
physicalism of this
sort denies that the theoretical and conceptual resources appropriate and
adequate for dealing with facts at the level of the underlying substrate or
realization level must be adequate as well for dealing with those at the
realized level (Putnam 1975, Boyd 1980). As noted above in response to the How
question, one can believe that all economic facts are physically realized
without thinking that the resources of the physical sciences provide all the
cognitive and conceptual tools we need for doing economics (Fodor 1974).
Nonreductive
physicalism has been challenged for its alleged failure to “pay its physicalist
dues” in reductive coin. It is faulted for supposedly not giving an adequate
account of how conscious properties are or could be realized by underlying
neural, physical or functional structures or processes (Kim 1987, 1998). Indeed
it has been charged with incoherence because of its attempt to combine a claim
of physical realization with the denial of the ability to spell out that
relation in a strict and a priori intelligible way (Jackson 2004).
However,
as noted above in discussion of the How question, nonreductive physicalists
reply by agreeing that some account of psycho-physical realization is indeed
needed, but adding that the relevant account may fall far short of a
priori deducibility,
yet still suffice to satisfy our legitimate explanatory demands (McGinn
1991, Van Gulick 1985). The issue remains under debate.
9.
Specific Theories of Consciousness
Although
there are many general metaphysical/ontological theories of consciousness, the
list of specific detailed theories about its nature is even longer and more
diverse. No brief survey could be close to comprehensive, but seven main types
of theories may help to indicate the basic range of options: higher-order
theories, representational theories, interpretative narrative theories, cognitive
theories, neural theories, quantum theories and nonphysical theories. The
categories are not mutually exclusive; for example, many cognitive theories
also propose a neural substrate for the relevant cognitive processes.
Nonetheless grouping them in the seven classes provides a basic overview.
9.1
Higher-order theories
Higher-order
(HO) theories analyze the notion of a conscious mental state in terms of
reflexive meta-mental self-awareness. The core idea is that what makes a mental
state M a conscious mental state is the fact that it is accompanied by a
simultaneous and non-inferential higher-order (i.e., meta-mental) state whose
content is that one is now in M. Having a conscious desire for some chocolate
involves being in two mental states; one must have both a desire for some
chocolate and also a higher-order state whose content is that one is now having
just such a desire. Unconscious mental states are unconscious precisely in that
we lack the relevant higher-order states about them. Their being unconscious
consists in the fact that we are not reflexively and directly aware of being in
them. (See the entry on higher-order
theories of consciousness.)
Higher-order
theories come in two main variants that differ concerning the psychological
mode of the relevant conscious-making meta-mental states. Higher-order thought
(HOT) theories take the required higher-order state to be an assertoric
thought-like meta-state (Rosenthal 1986, 1993). Higher-order perception (HOP)
theories take them to be more perception-like and associated with a kind of
inner sense and intra-mental monitoring systems of some sort (Armstrong 1981,
Lycan 1987, 1996).
Each has
its relative strengths and problems. HOT theorists note that we have no organs
of inner sense and claim that we experience no sensory qualities other than
those presented to us by outer directed perception. HOP theorists on the other
hand can argue that their view explains some of the additional conditions
required by HO accounts as natural consequences of the perception-like nature
of the relevant higher-order states. In particular the demands that the
conscious-making meta-state be noninferential and simultaneous with its lower
level mental object might be explained by the parallel conditions that
typically apply to perception. We perceive what is happening now, and we do so
in a way that involves no inferences, at least not any explicit personal-level
inferences. Those conditions are no less necessary on the HOT view but are left
unexplained by it, which might seem to give some explanatory advantage to the
HOP model (Lycan 2004, Van Gulick 2000), though some HOT theorists argue
otherwise (Carruthers 2000).
Whatever
their respective merits, both HOP and HOT theories face some common challenges,
including what might be called thegenerality
problem. Having a
thought or perception of a given item X—be it a rock, a pen or a
potato—does not in general make X a conscious X.
Seeing or thinking of the potato on the counter does not make it a conscious
potato. Why then should having a thought or perception of a given desire or a
memory make it a conscious desire or memory (Dretske 1995, Byrne 1997). Nor
will it suffice to note that we do not apply the term “conscious” to rocks or
pens that we perceive or think of, but only to mental states that we perceive
or think of (Lycan 1997, Rosenthal 1997). That may be true, but what is needed
is some account of why it is appropriate to do so.
The
higher-order view is most obviously relevant to the meta-mental forms of
consciousness, but some of its supporters take it to explain other types of
consciousness as well, including the more subjective what it's like and
qualitative types. One common strategy is to analyze qualia as mental features
that are capable of occurring unconsciously; for example they might be
explained as properties of inner states whose structured similarity relations
given rise to beliefs about objective similarities in the world (Shoemaker
1975, 1990). Though unconscious qualia can play that functional role, there
need be nothing that it is like to be in a state that has them (Nelkin 1989,
Rosenthal 1991, 1997). According to the HO theorist, what-it's-likeness enters only when we become aware of
that first-order state and its qualitative properties by having an appropriate
meta-state directed at it.
Critics
of the HO view have disputed that account, and some have argued that the notion
of unconscious qualia on which it relies is incoherent (Papineau 2002). Whether
or not such proposed HO accounts of qualia are successful, it is important to
note that most HO advocates take themselves to be offering a comprehensive
theory of consciousness, or at least the core of such a general theory, rather
than merely one limited to some special meta-mental forms of it.
Other
variants of HO theory go beyond the standard HOT and HOP versions including
some that analyze consciousness in terms of dispositional rather than occurrent
higher-order thoughts (Carruthers 2000). Others appeal to implicit rather than
explicit higher-order understanding and weaken or remove the standard
assumption that the meta-state must be distinct and separate from its
lower-order object (Gennaro 1995, Van Gulick 2000, 2004) with such views overlapping
with so called reflexive theories discussed in the section. Other variants of
HO theory continue to be offered, and debate between supporters and critics of
the basic approach remains active. (See the recent papers in Gennaro 2004.)
9.2
Reflexive theories
Reflexive
theories, like higher-order theories, imply a strong link between consciousness
and self-awareness. They differ in that they locate the aspect of
self-awareness directly within the conscious state itself rather than in a
distinct meta-state directed at it. The idea that conscious states involve a
double intentionality goes back at least to Brentano (1874) in the 19th
century. The conscious state is intentionally directed at an object outside
itself—such as a tree or chair in the case of a conscious perception—as well as
intentionally directed at itself. One and the same state is both an
outer-directed awareness and an awareness of itself. Several recent theories
have claimed that such reflexive awareness is a central feature of conscious mental
states. Some view themselves as variants of higher-order theory (Gennaro 2004,
2012) while others reject the higher-order category and describe their theories
as presenting a “same-order” account of consciousness as self-awareness
(Kriegel 2009). Yet others challenge the level distinction by analyzing the
meta-intentional content as implicit in the phenomenal first-order content of
conscious states, as in so called Higher-Order Global State models (HOGS) (Van
Gulick 2004,2006). A sample of papers, some supporting and some attacking the
reflexive view can be found in Krigel and Williford (2006).
9.3
Representationalist theories
Almost
all theories of consciousness regard it as having representational features,
but so called representationalist theories are defined by the stronger view
that its representational features exhaust its mental features (Harman 1990,
Tye 1995, 2000). According to the representationalist, conscious mental states
have no mental properties other than their representational properties. Thus
two conscious or experiential states that share all their representational
properties will not differ in any mental respect.
The exact
force of the claim depends on how one interprets the idea of being
“representationally the same” for which there are many plausible alternative
criteria. One could define it coarsely in terms of satisfaction or truth
conditions, but understood in that way the representationalist thesis seems
clearly false. There are too many ways in which states might share their satisfaction
or truth conditions yet differ mentally, including those that concern their
mode of conceptualizing or presenting those conditions.
At the
opposite extreme, one could count two states as representationally distinct if
they differed in any features that played a role in their representational
function or operation. On such a liberal reading any differences in the bearers
of content would count as representational differences even if they bore the
same intentional or representational content; they might differ only in their means or mode of representation not their content.
Such a
reading would of course increase the plausibility of the claim that a conscious
state's representational properties exhaust its mental properties but at the
cost of significantly weakening or even trivializing the thesis. Thus the
representationalist seems to need an interpretation of representational
sameness that goes
beyond mere satisfaction conditions and reflects all the intentional or
contentful aspects of representation without being sensitive to mere
differences in underlying non-contentful features of the processes at the
realization level. Thus most representationalists provide conditions for
conscious experience that include both a content condition plus some further
causal role or format requirements (Tye 1995, Dretske 1995, Carruthers 2000).
Other representationalists accept the existence of qualia but treat them as
objective properties that external objects are represented as having, i.e.,
they treat them as represented properties rather than as properties
of representations or
mental states (Dretske 1995, Lycan 1996).
Representationalism
can be understood as a qualified form of eliminativism insofar as it denies the
existence of properties of a sort that conscious mental states are commonly
thought to have—or at least seem to have—namely those that are mental but not
representational. Qualia, at least if understood as intrinsic monadic
properties of conscious states accessible to introspection, would seem to be the
most obvious targets for such elimination. Indeed part of the motivation for
representationalism is to show that one can accommodate all the facts about
consciousness, perhaps within a physicalist framework, without needing to find
room for qualia or any other apparently non-representational mental properties
(Dennett 1990, Lycan 1996, Carruthers 2000).
Representationalism
has been quite popular in recent years and had many defenders, but it remains
highly controversial and intuitions clash about key cases and thought
experiments (Block 1996). In particular the possibility of inverted qualia
provides a crucial test case. To anti-representationalists, the mere logical
possibility of inverted qualia shows that conscious states can differ in a
significant mental respect while coinciding representationally.
Representationalists in reply deny either the possibility of such inversion or
its alleged import (Dretske 1995, Tye 2000).
Many
other arguments have been made for and against representationalism, such as those
concerning perceptions in different sense modalities of one and the same state
of affairs—seeing and feeling the same cube—which might seem to involve mental
differences distinct from how the relevant states represent the world to be
(Peacocke 1983, Tye 2003). In each case, both sides can muster strong
intuitions and argumentative ingenuity. Lively debate continues.
9.4
Narrative Interpretative Theories
Some
theories of consciousness stress the interpretative nature of facts about
consciousness. According to such views, what is or is not conscious is not
always a determinate fact, or at least not so independent of a larger context
of interpretative judgments. The most prominent philosophical example is the
Multiple Drafts Model (MDM) of consciousness, advanced by Daniel Dennett
(1991). It combines elements of both representationalism and higher-order
theory but does so in a way that varies interestingly from the more standard
versions of either providing a more interpretational and less strongly realist
view of consciousness.
The MDM
includes many distinct but interrelated features. Its name reflects the fact
that at any given moment content fixations of many sorts are occurring
throughout the brain. What makes some of these contents conscious is not that they
occur in a privileged spatial or functional location—the so called “Cartesian
Theater”—nor in a special mode or format, all of which the MDM denies. Rather
it a matter of what Dennett calls “cerebral celebrity”, i.e., the degree to
which a given content influences the future development of other contents
throughout the brain, especially with regard to how those effects are manifest
in the reports and behaviors that the person makes in response to various
probes that might indicate her conscious state. One of the MDM's key claims is
that different probes (e. g., being asked different questions or being in
different contexts that make differing behavioral demands) may elicit different
answers about the person's conscious state. Moreover, according to the MDM
there may be no probe-independent fact of the matter about what the person's
conscious state really was. Hence the “multiple” of the Multiple Drafts Model.
The MDM
is representationalist in that it analyzes consciousness in terms of content
relations. It also denies the existence of qualia and thus rejects any attempt
to distinguish conscious states from nonconscious states by their presence. It
rejects as well the notion of the self as an inner observer, whether located in
the Cartesian Theater or elsewhere. The MDM treats the self as an emergent or
virtual aspect of the coherent roughly serially narrative that is constructed
through the interactive play of contents in the system. Many of those contents
are bound together at the intentional level as perceptions or fixations from a
relatively unified and temporally extended point of view, i.e., they cohere in
their contents as if they were the experiences of a ongoing self. But it is the
order of dependence that is crucial to the MDM account. The relevant contents
are not unified because they are all observed by a single self, but just the
converse. It is because they are unified and coherent at the level of content
that they count as the experiences of a single self, at least of a single
virtual self.
It is in
this respect that the MDM shares some elements with higher-order theories. The
contents that compose the serial narrative are at least implicitly those of an
ongoing if virtual self, and it is they that are most likely to be expressed in
the reports the person makes of her conscious state in response to various
probes. They thus involve a certain degree of reflexivity or self-awareness of
the sort that is central to higher-order theories, but the higher-order aspect
is more an implicit feature of the stream of contents rather than present in
distinct explicit higher-order states of the sort found in standard HO
theories.
Dennett's
MDM has been highly influential but has also drawn criticism, especially from
those who find it insufficiently realist in its view of consciousness and at
best incomplete in achieving its stated goal to fully explain it (Block 1994,
Dretske 1994, Levine 1994). Many of its critics acknowledge the insight and
value of the MDM, but deny that there are no real facts of consciousness other
than those captured by it (Rosenthal 1994, Van Gulick 1994, Akins 1996).
From a
more empirical perspective, the neuroscientist Michael Gazzaniga (2011) has
introduced the idea of an “interpreter module” based in the left hemisphere
that makes sense of our actions in any inferential way and constructs an
ongoing narrative of our actions and experience. Though the theory is not
intended as a complete theory of consciousness, it accords a major role to such
interpretative narrative activity.
9.5
Cognitive Theories
A number
theories of consciousness associate it with a distinct cognitive architecture
or with a special pattern of activity with that structure.
Global
Workspace. A major psychological example of the cognitive approach is the
Global Workspace theory. As initially developed by Bernard Baars (1988)) global
workspace theory describes consciousness in terms of a competition among
processors and outputs for a limited capacity resource that “broadcasts”
information for widespread access and use. Being available in that way to the
global workspace makes information conscious at least in the access sense. It
is available for report and the flexible control of behavior. Much like
Dennett's “cerebral celebrity”, being broadcast in the workspace makes contents
more accessible and influential with respect to other contents and other
processors. At the same time the original content is strengthened by recurrent
support back from the workspace and from other contents with which it coheres.
The capacity limits on the workspace correspond to the limits typically placed
on focal attention or working memory in many cognitive models.
The model
has been further developed with proposed connections to particular neural and
functional brain systems by Stanislas Dehaene and others (2000). Of special
importance is the claim that consciousness in both the access and phenomenal
sense occurs when and only when the relevant content enters the larger global
network involving both primary sensory areas as well as many other areas
including frontal and parietal areas associated with attention. Dehaene claims
that conscious perception begins only with the “ignition” of that larger global
network; activity in the primary sensory areas will not suffice no matter how
intense or recurrent (though see the contrary view of Victor Lamme in section
9.7).
Attended
Intermediate Representation. Another cognitive theory is Jesse Prinz's
(2012) Attended Intermediate level Representation theory (AIR). The theory is a
neuro-cognitive hybrid account of conscious. According to AIR theory, a
conscious perception must meet both cognitive and neural conditions. It must be
a representation of a perceptually intermediate property which Prinz argues are
the only properties of which we are aware in conscious experience—we experience
only basic features of external objects such as colors, shapes, tones, and
feels. According to Prinz, our awareness of higher level properties—such as
being a pine tree or my car keys—is wholly a matter of judging and not of conscious
experience. Hence the Intermediate Representational (IR) aspect of AIR. To be
conscious such a represented content must also be Attended (the A aspect of
AIR). Prinz proposes a particular neural substrate for each component. He
identifies the intermediate level representations with gamma (40–80hz) vector
activity in sensory cortex and the attentional component with synchronized
oscillations that can incorporate that gamma vector activity.
9.6
Information Integration Theory
The
integration of information from many sources is an important feature of
consciousness and, as noted above (section 6.4), is often cited as one of its
major functions. Content integration plays an important role in various
theories especially global workspace theory (section 9.3). However, a proposal
by the neuroscientist Giulio Tononi (2008) goes further in identifying
consciousness with integrated information and asserting that information
integration of the relevant sort is both necessary and sufficient for
consciousness regardless of the substrate in which it is realized (which need
not be neural or biological). According to Tononi's Integrated Information
Theory (IIT), consciousness is a purely information-theoretic property of
systems. He proposes a mathematical measure φ that aims to measure not merely
the information in the parts of a given system but also the information
contained in the organization of the system over and above that in its parts. φ
thus corresponds to the system's degree of informational integration. Such a
system can contain many overlapping complexes and the complex with the highest
φ value will be conscious according to IIT.
According
to IIT, consciousness varies in quantity and comes in many degrees which
correspond to φ values. Thus even a simple system such a single photo diode
will be conscious to some degree if it is not contained within a larger
complex. In that sense, IIT implies a form of panpsychism that Tononi
explicitly endorses. According to IIT, the quality of the relevant consciousness
is determined by the totality of informational relations within the relevant
integrated complex. Thus IIT aims to explain both the quantity and quality of
phenomenal consciousness. Other neuroscientists, notably Christof Koch, have
also endorsed the IIT approach (Koch 2012).
9.7
Neural Theories
Neural
theories of consciousness come in many forms, though most in some way concern
the so called “neural correlates of consciousness” or NCCs. Unless one is a
dualist or other non-physicalist, more than mere correlation is required; at
least some NCCs must be the essential substrates of consciousness. An
explanatory neural theory needs to explain why or how the relevant correlations
exist, and if the theory is committed to physicalism that will require showing
how the underlying neural substrates could be identical with their neural
correlates or at least realize them by satisfying the required roles or
conditions (Metzinger 2000).
Such
theories are diverse not only in the neural processes or properties to which
they appeal but also in the aspects of consciousness they take as their
respective explananda. Some are based on high-level systemic features of the
brain, but others focus on more specific physiological or structural
properties, with corresponding differences in their intended explanatory
targets. Most in some way aim to connect with theories of consciousness at
other levels of description such as cognitive, representational or higher-order
theories.
A
sampling of recent neural theories might include models that appeal to global
integrated fields (Kinsbourne), binding through synchronous oscillation (Singer
1999, Crick and Koch 1990), NMDA-mediated transient neural assemblies (Flohr
1995), thalamically modulated patterns of cortical activation (Llinas 2001), reentrant
cortical loops (Edelman 1989), comparator mechanisms that engage in continuous
action-prediction-assessment loops between frontal and midbrain areas (Gray
1995), left hemisphere based interpretative processes (Gazzaniga 1988), and
emotive somatosensory hemostatic processes based in the frontal-limbic nexus
(Damasio 1999) or in the periaqueductal gray (Panksepp 1998).
In each
case the aim is to explain how organization and activity at the relevant neural
level could underlie one or another major type or feature of consciousness.
Global fields or transient synchronous assemblies could underlie the
intentional unity of phenomenal consciousness. NMDA-based plasticity, specific
thalamic projections into the cortex, or regular oscillatory waves could all contribute
to the formation of short term but widespread neural patterns or regularities
needed to knit integrated conscious experience out of the local activity in
diverse specialized brain modules. Left hemisphere interpretative processes
could provide a basis for narrative forms of conscious self-awareness. Thus it
is possible for multiple distinct neural theories to all be true, with each
contributing some partial understanding of the links between conscious
mentality in its diverse forms and the active brain at its many levels of
complex organization and structure.
One
particular recent controversy has concerned the issue of whether global or
merely local recurrent activity is sufficient for phenomenal consciousness.
Supporters of the global neuronal workspace model (Dehaene 2000) have argued
that consciousness of any sort can occur only when contents are activated with
a large scale pattern of recurrent activity involving frontal and parietal
areas as well as primary sensory areas of cortex. Others in particular the
psychologist Victor Lamme (2006) and the philosopher Ned Block (2007) have
argued that local recurrent activity between higher and lower areas within
sensory cortex (e.g. with visual cortex) can suffice for phenomenal
consciousness even in the absence of verbal reportability and other indicators
of access consciousness.
9.8
Quantum theories
Other
physical theories have gone beyond the neural and placed the natural locus of
consciousness at a far more fundamental level, in particular at the micro-physical
level of quantum phenomena. According to such theories, the nature and basis of
consciousness can not be adequately understood within the framework of
classical physics but must be sought within the alternative picture of physical
reality provided by quantum mechanics. The proponents of the quantum
consciousness approach regard the radically alternative and often
counterintuitive nature of quantum physics as just what is needed to overcome
the supposed explanatory obstacles that confront more standard attempts to
bridge the psycho-physical gap.
Again
there are a wide range of specific theories and models that have been proposed,
appealing to a variety of quantum phenomena to explain a diversity of features
of consciousness. It would be impossible to catalog them here or even explain
in any substantial way the key features of quantum mechanics to which they
appeal. However, a brief selective survey may provide a sense, however partial
and obscure, of the options that have been proposed.
The
physicist Roger Penrose (1989, 1994) and the anesthesiologist Stuart Hameroff
(1998) have championed a model according to which consciousness arises through
quantum effects occurring within subcellular structures internal to neurons
known as microtubules. The model
posits so called “objective
collapses” which involve the quantum system moving from a
superposition of multiple possible states to a single definite state, but
without the intervention of an observer or measurement as in most quantum
mechanical models. According to the Penrose and Hameroff, the environment
internal to the microtubules is especially suitable for such objective
collapses, and the resulting self-collapses produce a coherent flow regulating
neuronal activity and making non-algorithmic mental processes possible.
The
psychiatrist Ian Marshall has offered a model that aims to explain the coherent
unity of consciousness by appeal to the production within the brain of a
physical state akin to that of aBose-Einstein
condensate. The latter is a quantum phenomenon in which a
collection of atoms acts as a single coherent entity and the distinction
between discrete atoms is lost. While brain states are not literally examples
of Bose-Einstein condensates, reasons have been offered to show why brains are
likely to give rise to states that are capable of exhibiting a similar
coherence (Marshall and Zohar 1990).
A basis
for consciousness has also been sought in the holistic nature of quantum mechanics and the
phenomenon of entanglement, according to
which particles that have interacted continue to have their natures depend upon
each other even after their separation. Unsurprisingly these models have been
targeted especially at explaining the coherence of consciousness, but they have
also been invoked as a more general challenge to the atomistic conception of
traditional physics according to which the properties of wholes are to be
explained by appeal to the properties of their parts plus their mode of
combination, a method of explanation that might be regarded as unsuccessful to
date in explaining consciousness (Silberstein 1998, 2001).
Others
have taken quantum mechanics to indicate that consciousness is an absolutely
fundamental property of physical reality, one that needs to be brought in at
the very most basic level (Stapp 1993). They have appealed especially to the
role of the observer in the collapse of the wave function, i.e., the collapse
of quantum reality from a superposition of possible states to a single definite
state when a measurement is made. Such models may or may not embrace a form of
quasi-idealism, in which the very existence of physical reality depends upon
its being consciously observed.
There are
many other quantum models of consciousness to be found in the literature—some
advocating a radically revisionist metaphysics and others not—but these four
provide a reasonable, though partial, sample of the alternatives.
9.9
Non-physical theories
Most
specific theories of consciousness—whether cognitive, neural or quantum mechanical—aim
to explain or model consciousness as a natural feature of the physical world.
However, those who reject a physicalist ontology of consciousness must find
ways of modeling it as a nonphysical aspect of reality. Thus those who adopt a
dualist or anti-physicalist metaphysical view must in the end provide specific
models of consciousness different from the five types above. Both substance
dualists and property dualists must develop the details of their theories in
ways that articulate the specific natures of the relevant non-physical features
of reality with which they equate consciousness or to which they appeal in
order to explain it.
A variety
of such models have been proposed including the following. David Chalmers
(1996) has offered an admittedly speculative version of panpsychism which
appeals to the notion of information not only to explain psycho-physical
invariances between phenomenal and physically realized information spaces but
also to possibly explain the ontology of the physical as itself derived from
the informational (a version of “it from bit” theory). In a somewhat similar
vein, Gregg Rosenberg has (2004) proposed an account of consciousness that
simultaneously addresses the ultimate categorical basis of causal relations. In
both the causal case and the conscious case, Rosenberg argues the
relational-functional facts must ultimately depend upon a categorical
non-relational base, and he offers a model according to which causal relations
and qualitative phenomenal facts both depend upon the same base. Also, as noted
just above (section 9.8), some quantum theories treat consciousness as a
fundamental feature of reality (Stapp 1993), and insofar as they do so, they
might be plausibly classified as non-physical theories as well.
10.
Conclusion
A
comprehensive understanding of consciousness will likely require theories of
many types. One might usefully and without contradiction accept a diversity of
models that each in their own way aim respectively to explain the physical,
neural, cognitive, functional, representational and higher-order aspects of
consciousness. There is unlikely to be any single theoretical perspective that
suffices for explaining all the features of consciousness that we wish to
understand. Thus a synthetic and pluralistic approach may provide the best road
to future progress.
Selected
from --https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consciousness/
** **
1608
hours. I read this once already. I will now go back and parse it to make it
easier to read as a whole unit (for what I need) rather than in outlined
sections.
No comments:
Post a Comment