10 January 2015

Notes - something will be done / good enough


         You shared the BBC Future article on Free Will on your Facebook page yesterday and you need to have this in your notes as a reminder from where to think. - Amorella

** **
SUNDAY, DEC 28, 2014 07:00 AM EST

The truth about free will: Does it actually exist?

Acclaimed philosopher Daniel Dennett explains why free will is much more complicated than many people believe

DAVID EDMONDS AND NIGEL WARBURTON

The following interview is excerpted from "Philosophy Bites Again"

David Edmonds: One way to exercise my freedom would be to act unpredictably, perhaps not to have a typical introduction to a “Philosophy Bites” interview, or to cut it abruptly short mid-sentence. That’s the view of the famous philosopher and cognitive scientist, Daniel Dennett. He also believes that humans can have free will, even if the world is determinist, in other words, governed by causal laws, and he…

Nigel Warburton: The topic we’re focusing on is “Free Will Worth Wanting.” That seems a strange way in to free will. Usually, the free will debate is over whether we have free will, not whether we want it, or whether it’s worth wanting. How did you come at it from this point of view?

Daniel Dennett: I came to realize that many of the issues that philosophers love to talk about in the free will debates were irrelevant to anything important. There’s a bait-and-switch that goes on. I don’t think any topic is more anxiety provoking, or more genuinely interesting to everyday people, than free will But then philosophers replace the interesting issues with technical, metaphysical issues. Who cares? We can define lots of varieties of free will that you can’t have, or that are inconsistent with determinism. But so what? The question is, ‘Should you regret, or would you regret not having free will?’ Yes. Are there many senses of free will? Yes. Philosophers have tended to concentrate on varieties that are perhaps more tractable by their methods, but they’re not important.

NW: The classic description of the problem is this: ‘If we can explain every action through a series of causal precedents, there is no space for free will.’ What’s wrong with that description?

DD: It’s completely wrong. There’s plenty of space for free will: determinism and free will are not incompatible at all.

The problem is that philosophers have a very simplistic idea of causation. They think that if you give the lowest-level atomic explanation, then you have given a complete account of the causation: that’s all the causation there is. In fact, that isn’t even causation in an interesting sense.

NW: How is that simplistic? After all , at the level of billiard balls on a table, one ball hits another one and it causes the second one to move. Neither ball has any choice about whether it moved; their paths were determined physically.

DD: The problem with that is that it ignores all of the higher-level forms of causation which are just as real and just as important. Suppose you had a complete atom-by-atom history of every giraffe that ever lived, and every giraffe ancestor that ever lived. You wouldn’t have an answer to the question of why they have long necks. There is indeed a causal explanation, but it’s lost in those details. You have to go to a different level in order to explain why the giraffe developed its long neck. That’s the notion of causation that matters for free will.

NW: Assuming that you’re not going to rely on Aesop here, how did the giraffe get its long neck?

DD: The lineage of giraffe-like animals gradually got longer necks because those that happened to have slightly longer necks had a fitness advantage over those with shorter necks. That’s where the explanation lies. Why is that true? That’s still a vexed question. Maybe the best answer is not the obvious one that they got long necks so that they could reach higher leaves. Rather, they evolved long necks because they needed them to drink because they had long legs, and they evolved long legs because they provided a better defense against lions.

NW: So that’s an evolutionary hypothesis about giraffes’ necks. How does it shed any light on the free will debate?

DD: If I want to know why you pulled the trigger, I won’t learn that by having an atom-by-atom account of what went on in your brain. I’d have to go to a higher level: I’d have to go to the intentional stance in psychology Here’s a very simple analogy: you’ve got a hand calculator and you put in a number, and it gives the answer 3.333333E. Why did it do that? Well, if you tap in ten divided by three, and the answer is an infinite continuing decimal, the calculator gives an ‘E’.
Now, if you want to understand which cases this will happen to, don’t examine each and every individual transistor: use arithmetic. Arithmetic tells you which set of cases will give you an ‘E’. Don’t think that you can answer that question by electronics. That’s the wrong level. The same is true with playing computer chess. Why did the computer move its bishop? Because otherwise its queen would have been captured. That’s the level at which you answer that question.

NW: We’re often interested in intention where this is linked to moral or legal responsibility. And some cases depend on information that we get about people’s brains. For example, there are cases where people had brain lesions that presumably had some causal impact on their criminal behaviour.

DD: I’m so glad you raised that because it perfectly illus­trates a deep cognitive illusion that’s been fostered in the field for a generation and more. People say, ‘Whenever we have a physiological causal account, we don’t hold somebody responsible.’ Well, might that be because whenever people give a physiological causal account, these are always cases of disability or pathology? You never see a physiological account of somebody getting something tight. Supposing we went into Andrew Wiles’ brain and got a perfect physiological account of how he proved Fermat’s Last Theorem. Would that show that he’s not responsible for his proof? Of course not. It’s just that we never give causal physiological-level accounts of psychological events when they go right.

NW: I’m still having trouble understanding what an intention is. We usually think of intentions as introspectible mental events that precede actions. That doesn’t seem to be quite what you mean by an intention.

DO: When discussing the ‘intentional stance’, the word ‘intention’ means something broader than that. It refers to states that have content. Beliefs, desires, and intentions are among the states that have content. To adopt the intentional stance towards a person-it’s usually a person, but it could be towards a cat, or even a computer, playing chess-is to adopt the perspective that you’re dealing with an agent who has beliefs and desires, and decides what to do, and what inten­tions to form, on the basis of a rational assessment of those beliefs and desires. It’s the stance that dominates Game Theory. When, in the twentieth century; John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern invented the theory of games, they pointed out that game theory reflects something fundamental in strategy. Robinson Crusoe on a desert island doesn’t need the intentional stance. If there’s something in the environment that’s like an agent-that you can treat as an agent-this changes the game. You have to start worrying about feedback loops. If you plan activities, you have to think: ‘If I do this, this agent might think of doing that in response, and what would be my response to that?’ Robinson Crusoe doesn’t have to be sneaky and tiptoe around in his garden worrying about what the cabbages will do when they see him coming. But if you’ve got another agent there, you do.

NW: So, Man Friday appears, and there are problems …

DO: As soon as Man Friday appears, then you need the intentional stance.

NW: So if you have the complexity of interaction that is characteristic of an intentional system, that’s sufficient for its having intentions. So there doesn’t seem to be any room for the mistake of anthropomorphism. Anthropomorphism, if the situation is complex enough, is simply the correct attitude to hold towards some inanimate things.

DD: We can treat a tree from the intentional stance, and think about what it needs, and what it wants, and what steps it takes to get what it needs and wants. This works to some degree. Of course, it doesn’t have a soul; it’s not conscious.
But there are certain patterns and reactions. Recently, we’ve learned that many varieties of trees have a capacity that gives them quasi-colour vision. When the light on them is predominantly reflected from green things they change the proportion of their energy that goes into growing tall We might say that they have sensed the competition and are taking a reasonable step to deal with the competition. Now, that’s a classic example of the intentional stance applied to a tree, for heaven’s sake! Fancier versions apply to everything from bacteria, through clams and fish and reptiles and higher animals, all the way to us. We are the paradigm cases.

What’s special about us is that we don’t just do things for reasons. Trees do things for reasons. But we represent the reasons and we reflect on them, and the idea of reflecting on reasons and representing reasons and justifying our reasons to each other informs us and governs the intentional stance. We grow up learning to trade reasons with our friends and family. We’re then able to direct that perspective at evolutionary history, at artifacts, at trees. And then we see the reasons that aren’t represented, but are active. Until you get the level of perspective where you can see reasons, you ‘re not going to see free will The difference between an organism that has free will and an organism that doesn’t has nothing to do with the atoms: you’ll never see it at the atomic level, ever. You have to go to the appropriate design level, and then it sticks out like a sore thumb.

NW: So we can adopt the intentional stance towards a chess-playing computer, and we probably ought to if we want to beat it at chess, but it doesn’t follow from that that it’s got free will, or agency?

DO: Exactly Those beings with free will are a sub-set of intentional systems. We say ‘free as a bird’, and birds have a certain sort of free will. But the free will of a bird is nothing compared to our free will, because the bird doesn’t have the cognitive system to anticipate and reflect on its anticipations. It doesn’t have the same sort of projectable future that we have; nor does it, of course, engage in the business of persuasion. One bird never talks another bird out of doing something. It may threaten it, but it won’t talk it out of something.

NW: So let’s go back to the original topic. What is the kind of free will worth wanting?

DO: It’s the kind of free will that gives us the political freedom to move about in a state governed by law and do what we want to do. Not everybody has that freedom. It is a precious commodity Think about promises. There are many good reasons to make promises: some long-term projects depend on promises, for example. Now, not everybody is equipped to make a promise. Being equipped to make a promise requires a sort of free will, and a sort of free will that is morally important. We can take it apart, we can understand, as an engineer might say; what the ‘specs’ are for a morally competent agent: you’ve got to be well informed, have well-ordered desires, and be movable by reasons. You have to be persuadable and be able to justify your views. And there are a few other abilities that are a little more surprising. You have to be particularly good at detecting the intent of other agents to manipulate you and you have to be able to fend off this manipulation. One thing we require of moral agents is that they are not somebody else’s puppet. If you want the buck to stop with you, then you have to protect yourself from other agents who might be trying to control you. In order to fend off manipulation, you should be a little bit unpredictable. So having a poker face is a very big part of being a moral agent. If you can’t help but reveal your state to the antique dealer when you walk into the store, then you’re going to be taken for a ride, you’re going to be manipulated. If you can’t help but reveal your beliefs and desires to everybody that comes along, you will be a defective, a disabled agent. In order to maximize getting what you want in life, don’t tell people exactly what you want.

NW: That’s a very cynical view of human nature! There’s an alternative account, surely, in which being open about what you feel allows people to take you for what you really are, not for some kind of avatar of yourself.

DD: Well, yes, there is that. But think about courtship. You see a woman and you fall head over heels in love with her. What ‘s about the worst thing you can do? Run panting up to her showing her that you’ve fallen head over heels in love.
First of all, you’ll probably scare her away, or she’ll be tempted by your very display of abject adoration to wrap you around her little finger. You don’t want that, so you keep something in reserve. Talleyrand once said that God gave men language so that they could conceal their thoughts from each other. I think that’s a deep observation about the role of language in communication. It’s essential to the understanding of communication that it’s an intentional act, where you decide which aspects of your world you want to inform people about and which you don’t.

NW: So freedom, of the important kind, of the kind worth wanting, is freedom from being manipulated. It’s about being in control of your life, you choosing to do things, rather than these things being chosen by somebody else?

DD: Yes. In order for us to be self-controllers, to be autono­mous in a strong sense, we have to make sure that we” re not being controlled by others. Now, the environment in general is not an agent, it’s not trying to control us. It’s only other agents that try to control us. And it’s important that we keep them at bay so that we can be autonomous. In order to do that, we have to have the capacity to surprise.

Excerpted from “Philosophy Bites Again” by David Edmonds and Nigel Warburton. Copyright © 2014 by David Edmonds and Nigel Warburton. Reprinted by arrangement with Oxford University Press, a division of Oxford University. All rights reserved.

Selected and edited from -  BBC Future - 09 January 2015 via (SalonDOTcom)
** **

         1108 hours. ‘Communication is an intentional act.’ I had not thought of communication in this way before. Obviously it is, even more so in misdirected communication with intent, i.e. “War is peace. Freedom is slavery. Ignorance is strength.” Yet, Freedom is in surveillance. I appreciate cameras on the streets because if I am robbed under such surveillance it is more likely the thief will be caught and hopefully punished for herorhis crime. Surveillance helps keep us safe. A baby monitor is a good example of this. Why would a ‘moral agent’ fear a surveillance camera? It is not a social free right to commit a crime against fellow human beings, or rather; it should not be in my mind, yet I learned to abhor the political totalitarian regimes that were a part of my childhood and I love Orwell and Huxley for pointing out their defects in Animal Farm, 1984 and Brave New World. Such are the contradictions in this human’s thoughts. What to do about it? Something will be done and we will most likely witness it.

         Post. - Amorella


         You have been home a while and noted the weather is going to be rain, sleet and snow tomorrow afternoon through Monday, thus you are at Kroger’s on Tylersville for items to make a soup or chili for a couple of meals or so. Dusk is settling into evening, and the simulated nearby church bells just finished their six o’clock chime. – Amorella

         1805 hours. The trip home was good with light traffic and mostly clear sky. We had lunch at Wendy’s in south Delaware as the boys were coming home from swimming lessons at the local YMCA. It has been another good family day. I really get a kick out of Owen and Brennan. I love to hear their language development. Kim, Paul and their Primrose School do a really good job in training them to speak clearly and distinctly with fun and games built in. Also, Owen is really considerate and polite. Brennan is almost three and not so much of either unless reminded. His favorite test word is still “No.” I caught him saying it a couple of times today and laughed and asked if he was joking while using the word. He admitted that sometimes he is.

         Carol made two ham and egg omelets for supper. After you watched “Elementary” and “Mysteries of Laura”. Carol is up reading with Jadah at her side and you are in the living room with Spooky for company. Both cats appear content that you are home – earlier a couple small pieces of ham helped. – Amorella

         2133 hours. When I was first reading the article above I found a couple of lines that immediately made me think of “To A Mouse” by Robert Burns.

** **
“To a Mouse”

By Robert Burns

On Turning up in Her Nest with the Plough, November, 1785

Wee, sleeket, cowran, tim’rous beastie,
O, what a panic’s in thy breastie!
Thou need na start awa sae hasty,
          Wi’ bickerin brattle!
I wad be laith to rin an’ chase thee
          Wi’ murd’ring pattle!

I’m truly sorry Man’s dominion
Has broken Nature’s social union,
An’ justifies that ill opinion,
          Which makes thee startle,
At me, thy poor, earth-born companion,
          An’ fellow-mortal!

I doubt na, whyles, but thou may thieve;
What then? poor beastie, thou maun live!
A daimen-icker in a thrave
          ’S a sma’ request:
I’ll get a blessin wi’ the lave,
          An’ never miss ’t!

Thy wee-bit housie, too, in ruin!
It’s silly wa’s the win’s are strewin!
An’ naething, now, to big a new ane,
          O’ foggage green!
An’ bleak December’s winds ensuin,
          Baith snell an’ keen!

Thou saw the fields laid bare an’ waste,
An’ weary Winter comin fast,
An’ cozie here, beneath the blast,
          Thou thought to dwell,
Till crash! the cruel coulter past
          Out thro’ thy cell.

That wee-bit heap o’ leaves an’ stibble
Has cost thee monie a weary nibble!
Now thou’s turn’d out, for a’ thy trouble,
          But house or hald,
To thole the Winter’s sleety dribble,
          An’ cranreuch cauld!

But Mousie, thou art no thy-lane,
In proving foresight may be vain:
The best laid schemes o’ Mice an’ Men
          Gang aft agley,
An’ lea’e us nought but grief an’ pain,
          For promis’d joy!

Still, thou art blest, compar’d wi’ me!
The present only toucheth thee:
But Och! I backward cast my e’e,
          On prospects drear!
An’ forward tho’ I canna see,
          I guess an’ fear!


Selected and edited from poetryfoundationDOTorg

** **

         The lines in the article are:

“We say ‘free as a bird’, and birds have a certain sort of free will. But the free will of a bird is nothing compared to our free will, because the bird doesn’t have the cognitive system to anticipate and reflect on its anticipations. It doesn’t have the same sort of projectable future that we have; nor does it, of course, engage in the business of persuasion.”

         I have found in more than fifty years of my life devoted to reading literature and poetry (and in the many subsequent re-readings) certain important human concepts continually pop up and indeed overlap. This overlapping shows me ‘truths’ are ‘felt and understood’ as well as studied scholarly and show evidence of a said ‘truth’. Both are valid as far as understanding the human condition is concerned. This is a reminder to me that ‘understanding’ can be more important than the ‘knowledge’ that leads to the understanding because knowledge is a different consideration than wisdom but using wisdom must show human understanding over the specific objective factual knowledge of the situation. Using wisdom (moral agent) demands free will.

         This is your point, but what is its purpose here (in the blog)? – Amorella

         2153 hours. Human freedom rests on the ability to use this freedom wisely. Freedom is not all encompassing; it is limited. For instance, the health and safety of the group supersedes the freedom of the individual within the group. Few would deny this but some human beings do. I do not have a say in human social rules but in my fiction I can use this as an argument for why the marsupial humanoid culture is as it is.

         Good enough; because you are showing how this is in your mind as you write. Post. - Amorella

No comments:

Post a Comment